id
stringlengths
1
260
contents
stringlengths
1
234k
21873
\section{Structure Induced by Commutative Operation is Commutative} Tags: Abstract Algebra, Commutativity, Pointwise Operations, Mappings, Mapping Theory \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {T, \circ}$ be an algebraic structure, and let $S$ be a set. Let $\struct {T^S, \oplus}$ be the structure on $T^S$ induced by $\circ$. Let $\circ$ be a commutative operation. Then the pointwise operation $\oplus$ induced on $T^S$ by $\circ$ is also commutative. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Let $\struct {T, \circ}$ be a commutative algebraic structure. Let $f, g \in T^S$. Then: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = \map {\paren {f \oplus g} } x | r = \map f x \circ \map g x | c = {{Defof|Pointwise Operation}} }} {{eqn | r = \map g x \circ \map f x | c = $\circ$ is commutative }} {{eqn | r = \map {\paren {g \oplus f} } x | c = {{Defof|Pointwise Operation}} }} {{end-eqn}} {{qed}} \end{proof}
21874
\section{Structure Induced by Commutative Ring Operations is Commutative Ring} Tags: Mapping Theory, Ring Theory, Rings of Mappings \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {R, +, \circ}$ be a commutative ring. Let $S$ be a set. Let $\struct {R^S, +', \circ'}$ be the structure on $R^S$ induced by $+'$ and $\circ'$. Then $\struct {R^S, +', \circ'}$ is a commutative ring. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} By Structure Induced by Ring Operations is Ring then $\struct {R^S, +', \circ'}$ is a ring. From Structure Induced by Commutative Operation is Commutative, so is the pointwise operation $\circ$ induces on $R^S$. The result follows by definition of commutative ring. {{qed}} Category:Rings of Mappings \end{proof}
21875
\section{Structure Induced by Group Operation is Group} Tags: Mapping Theory, Group Theory \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {G, \circ}$ be a group whose identity is $e$. Let $S$ be a set. Let $\struct {G^S, \oplus}$ be the structure on $G^S$ induced by $\circ$. Then $\struct {G^S, \oplus}$ is a group. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Taking the group axioms in turn: \end{proof}
21876
\section{Structure Induced by Permutation on Algebra Loop is not necessarily Algebra Loop} Tags: Operations Induced by Permutations, Algebra Loops \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {S, \circ}$ be an algebra loop. Let $\sigma: S \to S$ be a permutation on $S$. Let $\struct {S, \circ_\sigma}$ be the structure induced by $\sigma$ on $\circ$: :$\forall x, y \in S: x \circ_\sigma y := \map \sigma {x \circ y}$ Then $\struct {S, \circ_\sigma}$ is not necessarily also an algebra loop. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Consider the Cayley table of the algebra loop on $S = \set {e, a, b}$: :$\begin{array}{r|rrr} \circ & e & a & b \\ \hline e & e & a & b \\ a & a & b & e \\ b & b & e & a \\ \end{array}$ Consider the permutation on $S$: Let $\sigma$ denote the permutation on $S$ defined as: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = \map \sigma e | r = a }} {{eqn | l = \map \sigma a | r = e }} {{eqn | l = \map \sigma b | r = b }} {{end-eqn}} Then the Cayley table of the structure induced by $\sigma$ on $\circ$ is seen to be: :$\begin{array}{r|rrr} \circ & e & a & b \\ \hline e & a & e & b \\ a & e & b & a \\ b & b & a & e \\ \end{array}$ It is apparent by inspection that this is the Cayley table of a quasigroup. However, there is no identity element. Hence by definition $\struct {S, \circ_\sigma}$ is not an algebra loop. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21877
\section{Structure Induced by Permutation on Commutative Quasigroup is Commutative Quasigroup} Tags: Operations Induced by Permutations, Commutativity, Quasigroups, Quasigroup \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {S, \circ}$ be a quasigroup such that $\circ$ is a commutative operation. Let $\sigma: S \to S$ be a permutation on $S$. Let $\struct {S, \circ_\sigma}$ be the structure induced by $\sigma$ on $\circ$: :$\forall x, y \in S: x \circ_\sigma y := \map \sigma {x \circ y}$ Then $\struct {S, \circ_\sigma}$ is also a quasigroup such that $\circ_\sigma$ is a commutative operation. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} From Structure Induced by Permutation on Quasigroup is Quasigroup we have that $\struct {S, \circ_\sigma}$ is a quasigroup. Then we see that: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | q = \forall a, b \in S | l = a \circ_\sigma b | r = \map \sigma {a \circ b} | c = {{Defof|Operation Induced by Permutation}} }} {{eqn | r = \map \sigma {b \circ a} | c = {{Defof|Commutative Operation}} }} {{eqn | r = b \circ_\sigma a | c = {{Defof|Operation Induced by Permutation}} }} {{end-eqn}} {{qed}} \end{proof}
21878
\section{Structure Induced by Permutation on Quasigroup is Quasigroup} Tags: Operations Induced by Permutations, Semigroups, Quasigroups \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {S, \circ}$ be a quasigroup. Let $\sigma: S \to S$ be a permutation on $S$. Let $\struct {S, \circ_\sigma}$ be the structure induced by $\sigma$ on $\circ$: :$\forall x, y \in S: x \circ_\sigma y := \map \sigma {x \circ y}$ Then $\struct {S, \circ_\sigma}$ is also a quasigroup. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} By definition of quasigroup: :$\forall a, b \in S: \exists ! x \in S: x \circ a = b$ :$\forall a, b \in S: \exists ! y \in S: a \circ y = b$ Let $a, b \in S$. As $\sigma$ is a permutation, it is by definition both surjective and injective. We have that: :$\exists ! x: x \circ a = b$ Thus: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | q = \exists ! x \in S | l = \map \sigma {x \circ a} | r = b | c = }} {{eqn | ll= \leadsto | l = x \circ_\sigma a | r = b | c = {{Defof|Operation Induced by Permutation}} }} {{end-eqn}} Similarly, we have that: :$\exists ! x: a \circ x = b$ Thus: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | q = \exists ! x \in S | l = \map \sigma {a \circ x} | r = b | c = }} {{eqn | ll= \leadsto | l = a \circ_\sigma x | r = b | c = {{Defof|Operation Induced by Permutation}} }} {{end-eqn}} The result follows. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21879
\section{Structure Induced by Permutation on Semigroup is not necessarily Semigroup} Tags: Operations Induced by Permutations, Semigroups \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {S, \circ}$ be a semigroup. Let $\sigma: S \to S$ be a permutation on $S$. Let $\struct {S, \circ_\sigma}$ be the structure induced by $\sigma$ on $\circ$: :$\forall x, y \in S: x \circ_\sigma y := \map \sigma {x \circ y}$ Then $\struct {S, \circ_\sigma}$ is not necessarily itself a semigroup. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} From Operation Induced by Permutation on Magma is Closed we have that $\struct {S, \circ_\sigma}$ is a closed structure. Hence {{SemigroupAxiom|0}} holds. However, we have that Operation Induced by Permutation on Semigroup is not necessarily Associative. Hence {{SemigroupAxiom|1}} does not necessarily hold for $\struct {S, \circ_\sigma}$ Hence $\struct {S, \circ_\sigma}$ is not necessarily a semigroup. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21880
\section{Structure Induced by Ring Operations is Ring} Tags: Rings of Mappings, Ring Theory, Mappings, Examples of Rings, Rings, Mapping Theory \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {R, +, \circ}$ be a ring. Let $S$ be a set. Then $\struct {R^S, +', \circ'}$ is a ring, where $+'$ and $\circ'$ are the pointwise operations induced on $R^S$ by $+$ and $\circ$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} As $R$ is a ring, both $+$ and $\circ$ are closed on $R$ by definition. From Closure of Pointwise Operation on Algebraic Structure, it follows that both $+'$ and $\circ'$ are closed on $R^S$: :$\forall f, g \in R^S: f +' g \in R^S$ :$\forall f, g \in R^S: f \circ' g \in R^S$ By Structure Induced by Abelian Group Operation is Abelian Group, $\struct {R^S, +'}$ is an abelian group. By Structure Induced by Associative Operation is Associative, $\struct {R^S, \circ'}$ is a semigroup. From Pointwise Operation on Distributive Structure is Distributive, $\circ'$ is distributive over $+'$. The result follows by definition of ring. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21881
\section{Structure Induced by Ring with Unity Operations is Ring with Unity} Tags: Mapping Theory, Ring Theory, Rings of Mappings, Rings with Unity \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {R, +, \circ}$ be a ring with unity whose unity is $1_R$. Let $S$ be a set. Let $\struct {R^S, +', \circ'}$ be the structure on $R^S$ induced by $+'$ and $\circ'$. Then $\struct {R^S, +', \circ'}$ is a ring with unity whose unity is $f_{1_R}: S \to R$, defined by: :$\forall s \in S: \map {f_{1_R} } s = 1_R$ \end{theorem} \begin{proof} By Structure Induced by Ring Operations is Ring then $\struct {R^S, +', \circ'}$ is a ring. We have from Induced Structure Identity that the constant mapping $f_{1_R}: S \to R$ defined as: :$\forall x \in S: \map {f_{1_R} } x = 1_R$ is the identity for $\struct {R^S, \circ'}$. The result follows by definition of ring with unity and unity of ring. {{qed}} Category:Rings of Mappings Category:Rings with Unity \end{proof}
21882
\section{Structure Induced on Set of Self-Maps on Entropic Structure is Entropic} Tags: Entropic Structures, Pointwise Operations \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {S, \odot}$ be a magma. Let $\struct {S, \odot}$ be an entropic structure. Let $S^S$ be the set of all mappings from $S$ to itself. Let $\struct {S^S, \oplus}$ denote the algebraic structure on $S^S$ induced by $\odot$. Then $\struct {S^S, \oplus}$ is an entropic structure. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Recall the definition of algebraic structure on $S^S$ induced by $\odot$: Let $f: S \to S$ and $g: S \to S$ be self-maps on $S$, and thus elements of $S^S$. The pointwise operation on $S^S$ induced by $\odot$ is defined as: :$\forall x \in S: \map {\paren {f \oplus g} } x = \map f x \odot \map g x$ Let $f, g, p, q \in S^S$ be arbitrary. Let $x \in S$ be arbitrary. Then: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = \map {\paren {\paren {f \oplus g} \oplus \paren {p \oplus q} } } x | r = \paren {\map f x \odot \map g x} \odot \paren {\map p x \odot \map q x} | c = {{Defof|Pointwise Operation}} }} {{eqn | r = \paren {\map f x \odot \map p x} \odot \paren {\map g x \odot \map q x} | c = {{Defof|Entropic Structure}} }} {{eqn | r = \map {\paren {\paren {f \oplus p} \oplus \paren {g \oplus q} } } x | c = {{Defof|Pointwise Operation}} }} {{eqn | ll= \leadsto | l = \paren {f \oplus g} \oplus \paren {p \oplus q} | r = \paren {f \oplus p} \oplus \paren {g \oplus q} | c = Equality of Mappings }} {{end-eqn}} Hence the result by definition of entropic structure. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21883
\section{Structure of Cardinality 3+ where Every Permutation is Automorphism is Idempotent} Tags: Idempotence \begin{theorem} Let $S$ be a set whose cardinality is at least $3$. Let $\struct {S, \circ}$ be an algebraic structure on $S$ such that every permutation on $S$ is an automorphism on $\struct {S, \circ}$. Then $\circ$ is an idempotent operation. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} {{AimForCont}} $\circ$ is not idempotent. Then there exists $x \in S$ such that: :$\exists y \in S: x \circ x = y$ where $x \ne y$. Because there are at least $3$ distinct elements of $S$ {{hypothesis}}: :$\exists z \in S: z \ne x, z \ne y$ Let $f: S \to S$ be a permutation on $S$ such that: :$\map f x = x$ :$\map f y = z$ We have: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = z | r = \map f y | c = Definition of $f$ }} {{eqn | r = \map f {x \circ x} | c = {{hypothesis}}: $x \circ x = y$ }} {{eqn | r = \map f x \circ \map f x | c = {{hypothesis}}: $f$ is an automorphism }} {{eqn | r = x \circ x | c = Definition of $f$ }} {{eqn | r = y | c = {{hypothesis}}: $x \circ x = y$ }} {{end-eqn}} This contradicts our assertion that $x$ and $z$ are distinct. From Proof by Contradiction it follows that our assumption that $\circ$ is not idempotent must have been false. Hence $\circ$ is idempotent. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21884
\section{Structure of Inverse Completion of Commutative Semigroup} Tags: Commutative Semigroups, Inverse Completions \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {S, \circ}$ be a commutative semigroup. Let $\struct {C, \circ} \subseteq \struct {S, \circ}$ be the subsemigroup of cancellable elements of $\struct {S, \circ}$. Let $\struct {T, \circ'}$ be an inverse completion of $\struct {S, \circ}$. Then: :$T = S \circ' C^{-1}$ where: :$C^{-1}$ is the inverse of $C$ in $T$ :$S \circ' C^{-1}$ is the subset product of $S$ with $C^{-1}$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Let $a \in C$. {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = x | o = \in | r = S | c = }} {{eqn | ll= \leadsto | l = x | r = x \circ \paren {a \circ' a^{-1} } | c = {{Defof|Invertible Element}} }} {{eqn | ll= \leadsto | l = x | r = \paren {x \circ a} \circ' a^{-1} | c = {{Defof|Associative Operation}} }} {{eqn | ll= \leadsto | l = x | o = \in | r = S \circ' C^{-1} | c = {{Defof|Subset Product}} }} {{eqn | ll= \leadsto | l = S | o = \subseteq | r = S \circ' C^{-1} | c = {{Defof|Subset}} }} {{end-eqn}} Then: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = y | o = \in | r = C | c = }} {{eqn | ll= \leadsto | l = y^{-1} | o = \in | r = C^{-1} | c = {{Defof|Inverse of Subset of Monoid}} }} {{eqn | ll= \leadsto | l = y^{-1} | r = a \circ' a^{-1} \circ' y^{-1} | c = {{Defof|Invertible Element}} }} {{eqn | ll= \leadsto | l = y^{-1} | r = a \circ' \paren {y \circ' a}^{-1} | c = Inverse of Product }} {{eqn | ll= \leadsto | l = y^{-1} | r = a \circ' \paren {y \circ a}^{-1} | c = {{Defof|Extension of Operation}} }} {{eqn | ll= \leadsto | l = y^{-1} | o = \in | r = S \circ' C^{-1} | c = {{Defof|Subset Product}} }} {{eqn | ll= \leadsto | l = C^{-1} | o = \subseteq | r = S \circ' C^{-1} | c = {{Defof|Subset}} }} {{end-eqn}} Thus, as: :$C^{-1} \subseteq S \circ' C^{-1}$ and: :$S \subseteq S \circ' C^{-1}$ by Union is Smallest Superset it follows that: :$S \cup C^{-1} \subseteq S \circ' C^{-1}$ From Subset Product defining Inverse Completion of Commutative Semigroup is Commutative Semigroup: :$S \circ' C^{-1}$ is a commutative semigroup. So $S \circ' C^{-1}$ is a semigroup which contains $S \cup C^{-1}$. By definition of generator of semigroup, it follows that: :$\gen {S \cup C^{-1} } \subseteq S \circ' C^{-1}$ Let $z = x \circ' y^{-1} \in S \circ' C^{-1}$. Then by definition: :$x \in S$ and: :$y^{-1} \in C^{-1}$ and so by definition of generator of semigroup: :$x \circ' y^{-1} \in \gen {S \cup C^{-1} }$ Thus: $S \circ' C^{-1} \subseteq \gen {S \cup C^{-1} }$ By definition of set equality: :$S \circ' C^{-1} = \gen {S \cup C^{-1} }$ and so by definition of the inverse completion: :$T = S \circ' C^{-1}$ {{qed}} \end{proof}
21885
\section{Structure of Recurring Decimal} Tags: Number Theory \begin{theorem} Let $\dfrac 1 m$, when expressed as a decimal expansion, recur with a period of $p$ digits with no nonperiodic part. Let $\dfrac 1 n$, when expressed as a decimal expansion, terminate after $q$ digits. Then $\dfrac 1 {m n}$ has a nonperiodic part of $q$ digits, and a recurring part of $p$ digits. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Let $b \in \N_{>1}$ be the base we are working on. Note that $b^p \times \dfrac 1 m$ is the result of shifting the decimal point of $\dfrac 1 m$ by $p$ digits. Hence $b^p \times \dfrac 1 m - \dfrac 1 m$ is an integer, and $\paren {b^i - 1} \dfrac 1 m$ is not an integer for integers $0 < i < p$. Therefore $m \divides b^p - 1$. Also note that $b^q \times \dfrac 1 n$ is the result of shifting the decimal point of $\dfrac 1 n$ by $q$ digits. Hence $b^q \times \dfrac 1 n$ is an integer, and $b^j \times \dfrac 1 n$ is not an integer for integers $0 < j < q$. Therefore $n \divides b^q$ and $n \nmid b^{q - 1}$. Write $m x = b^p - 1$ and $n y = b^q$. Then $\dfrac 1 {m n} = \dfrac {x y} {\paren {b^p - 1} b^q}$. By Division Theorem: :$\exists! r, s \in \Z: x y = s \paren {b^p - 1} + r, 0 \le r < b^p - 1$ Then we would have: :$\dfrac 1 {m n} = \dfrac {s \paren {b^p - 1} + r} {\paren {b^p - 1} b^q} = \dfrac s {b^q} + \dfrac r {\paren {b^p - 1} b^q}$ which is a fraction with a nonperiodic part of $q$ digits equal to $s$, followed by a recurring part of $p$ digits equal to $r$. To show that the nonperiodic part and recurring part of $\dfrac 1 {m n}$ cannot be shorter, we must show: :$r \not \equiv s \pmod b$: or else the nonperiodic part could be shortened by at least $1$ digit :$\dfrac r {b^p - 1} \paren {b^i - 1}$ is not an integer for integers $0 < i < p$: or else the recurring part could be shortened to $i$ digits To show the first condition, suppose the contrary. Then: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = x y | r = s \paren {b^p - 1} + r }} {{eqn | o = \equiv | r = s \paren {b^p - 1} + s | rr= \pmod b }} {{eqn | o = \equiv | r = s b^p | rr= \pmod b }} {{eqn | o = \equiv | r = 0 | rr= \pmod b }} {{end-eqn}} From GCD with Remainder: :$\gcd \set {b, b^p - 1} = 1$ Since $x \divides b^p - 1$, by Divisor of One of Coprime Numbers is Coprime to Other: :$\gcd \set {b, x} = 1$ By Euclid's Lemma: :$b \divides y$ From $n y = b^q$: :$n \times \dfrac y b = b^{q - 1}$ so $n \divides b^{q - 1}$, which contradicts the properties of $n$. To show the second condition, suppose the contrary. Then: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = \paren {b^i - 1} \dfrac 1 m | r = \dfrac {n \paren {b^i - 1} } {m n} }} {{eqn | r = n \paren {b^i - 1} \paren {\dfrac s {b^q} + \dfrac r {\paren {b^p - 1} b^q} } }} {{eqn | r = \dfrac n {b^q} \paren {s \paren {b^i - 1} + \dfrac {r \paren {b^i - 1} } {b^p - 1} } }} {{end-eqn}} Both fractions are integers, so $\paren {b^i - 1} \dfrac 1 m$ is also an integer, which contradicts the properties of $\dfrac 1 m$. Hence the result. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21886
\section{Structure of Simple Algebraic Field Extension} Tags: Fields, Field Extensions \begin{theorem} Let $F / K$ be a field extension. Let $\alpha \in F$ be algebraic over $K$. Let $\mu_\alpha$ be the minimal polynomial of $\alpha$ over $K$. Let $K \sqbrk \alpha$ (resp. $\map K \alpha$) be the subring (resp. subfield) of $F$ generated by $K \cup \set \alpha$. Then: :$K \sqbrk \alpha = \map K \alpha \simeq K \sqbrk X / \gen {\mu_\alpha}$ where $\gen {\mu_\alpha}$ is the ideal of the ring of polynomial functions generated by $\mu_\alpha$. {{explain|Link to Generator needs refining}} Moreover: :$n := \index {\map K \alpha} K = \deg \mu_\alpha$ and: :$1, \alpha, \dotsc, \alpha^{n - 1}$ is a basis of $\map K \alpha$ over $K$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Define $\phi: K \sqbrk X \to K \sqbrk \alpha$ by: :$\map \phi f = \map f \alpha$ We have :$\map \phi f = 0 \iff \map f \alpha = 0 \iff \mu_\alpha \divides f$ where the last equivalence is proved in Minimal Polynomial. {{explain|Presumably $\mu_\alpha \vert f$ means divisibility -- clarification needed.}} {{refactor|The above needs to be extracted into a different page, as Minimal Polynomial is to be refactored: merged, probably, into somewhere else.}} Thus: :$\ker \phi = \set {f \in K \sqbrk X: \mu_\alpha \divides f} =: \gen {\mu_\alpha}$ By the corollary to Field Adjoined Set $\phi$ is surjective. So by the First Isomorphism Theorem, :$K \sqbrk X / \gen {\mu_\alpha} \simeq K \sqbrk \alpha$ By Principal Ideal of Principal Ideal Domain is of Irreducible Element iff Maximal: :$\gen {\mu_\alpha}$ is maximal. So $K \sqbrk \alpha$ is a field by Maximal Ideal iff Quotient Ring is Field. Also $K \sqbrk \alpha$ is the smallest ring containing $K \cup \set \alpha$. So because a field is a ring it is also the smallest field containing $K \cup \set \alpha$. This shows that $K \sqbrk \alpha = \map K \alpha$. By Field Adjoined Set: :$K \sqbrk \alpha = \set {\map f \alpha: f \in K \sqbrk X}$ where $K \sqbrk X$ is the ring of polynomial functions over $K$. From Division Theorem for Polynomial Forms over Field, for each $f \in K \sqbrk X$ there are $q, r \in K \sqbrk X$ such that: :$f = q \mu_\alpha + r$ and: :$\deg r < d =: \deg \mu_\alpha$ Therefore, since $\map {\mu_\alpha} \alpha = 0$, we have {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = K \sqbrk \alpha | r = \set {\map r \alpha: r \in K \sqbrk X, \ \deg r < \deg \mu_\alpha} }} {{eqn | r = \set {a_0 + a_1 \alpha + \dotsb + a_{d - 1} \alpha^{d - 1}: \alpha_0, \dotsc, \alpha_d \in K} }} {{end-eqn}} Therefore $1, \dotsc, \alpha^{d - 1}$ span $K \sqbrk \alpha / K$ as a vector space. Moreover if $s \in K \sqbrk X$, then $\map s \alpha = 0$ and $\deg s < \deg \mu_\alpha$ implies that $s = 0$. Thus $1, \dotsc, \alpha^{d - 1}$ are linearly independent. Therefore no non-zero $K$-combination of $1, \dotsc, \alpha^{d - 1}$ is zero. Therefore $\set {1, \dotsc, \alpha^{d - 1} }$ is a basis of $K \sqbrk \alpha / K$. The degree of $K \sqbrk \alpha / K$ is by definition the number of elements of a basis for $K \sqbrk \alpha / K$. Therefore: :$d = \deg \mu_\alpha = \index {K \sqbrk \alpha} K$ {{qed}} Category:Field Extensions \end{proof}
21887
\section{Structure under Left Operation is Semigroup} Tags: Left Operation, Examples of Semigroups \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {S, \gets}$ be an algebraic structure in which the operation $\gets$ is the left operation. Then $\struct {S, \gets}$ is a semigroup. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} We need to verify the semigroup axioms: {{:Axiom:Semigroup Axioms}} By the nature of the right operation, $\struct {S, \to}$ is closed: :$\forall x, y \in S: x \gets y = y \in S$ whatever $S$ may be. Hence {{SemigroupAxiom|0}} holds. From Right Operation is Associative, $\gets$ is associative. Hence {{SemigroupAxiom|1}} holds. So $\struct {S, \gets}$ is a semigroup. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21888
\section{Structure under Right Operation is Semigroup} Tags: Right Operation, Examples of Semigroups \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {S, \to}$ be an algebraic structure in which the operation $\to$ is the right operation. Then $\struct {S, \to}$ is a semigroup. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} We need to verify the semigroup axioms: {{:Axiom:Semigroup Axioms}} By the nature of the right operation, $\struct {S, \to}$ is closed: :$\forall x, y \in S: x \to y = y \in S$ whatever $S$ may be. Hence {{SemigroupAxiom|0}} holds. From Right Operation is Associative, $\to$ is associative. Hence {{SemigroupAxiom|1}} holds. So $\struct {S, \to}$ is a semigroup. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21889
\section{Structure with Element both Identity and Zero has One Element} Tags: Zero Elements, Identity Elements \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {S, \circ}$ be an algebraic structure. Let $z \in S$ such that $z$ is both an identity element and a zero element. Then: :$S = \set z$ \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Let $x \in S$. Then {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = x | r = x \circ z | c = {{Defof|Identity Element}} }} {{eqn | r = z | c = {{Defof|Zero Element}} }} {{end-eqn}} and so there is no other element of $S$ but $z$. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21890
\section{Sturm-Liouville Problem} Tags: \begin{theorem} Let: :$P \in C^\infty \map P x > 0$ :$Q \in C^0$ :$-\paren {P y'}' + Q y = \lambda y$ :$\map y a = \map y b = 0$ Then the Sturm-Liouville problem has an infinite sequence of eigenvalues $\set {\lambda^{\paren n} }$, and to each $\lambda^{\paren n}$ corresponds an eigenfunction $y^{\paren n}$, unique up to a constant factor. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} :$J \sqbrk y = \ds \int_a^b \paren {P y'^2 + Q y^2} \rd x$ :$\ds \int_a^b y^2 \rd x = 1$ :$\ds \int_a^b \paren {P y'^2 + Q y^2} \rd x > \int_a^b Q y^2 \rd x \ge M \int_a^b y^2 \rd x = M$ :$M = \min \limits_{a \mathop \le x \mathop \le b} \map Q x$ Assume $a = 0$, $b = \pi$. Choose $\set {\map {\phi_n} x} = \set {\sin n x}$ For $k \ne l$ we have: :$\ds \int_0^\pi \sin k x \sin l x \rd x = 0$ :$\ds \int_0^\pi \paren {\sum_{k \mathop = 1}^n \alpha_k \sin k x}^2 \rd x = \dfrac \pi 2 \sum_{k \mathop = 1}^n \alpha_k^2 = 1$ :$\ds \map {J_n} {\alpha_1, \ldots, \alpha_n} = \int_o^\pi \paren {\map P {\sum_{k \mathop = 1}^n \alpha_k \sin k x}'^2 + \map Q {\sum_{k \mathop = 1}^n \alpha_k \sin k x}^2} \rd x$ {{explain|The scope of the $'$ and ${}^2$ in $\ds \map P {\sum_{k \mathop {{=}} 1}^n \alpha_k \sin k x}'^2$ needs to be clarified in the above}} :$\ds \map {y_n^{\paren 1} } x = \sum_{k \mathop = 1}^n \alpha_k^{\paren 1} \sin k x$ :$\set {\lambda_n^{\paren 1} }$ :$\set {y_n^{\paren 1} }$ :$\map {J_n} {\alpha_1, \ldots, \alpha_n} = \map {J_{n + 1} } {\alpha_1, \ldots, \alpha_n, 0}$ :$\lambda_{n + 1}^{\paren 1} \le \lambda_n^{\paren 1}$ :$\lambda^{\paren 1} = \lim_{n \mathop \to \infty} \lambda_n^{\paren 1}$ :$\ds \lambda_n^{\paren 1} = \int_0^\pi \paren {P y_n'^2 + Q y_n^2} \rd x$ :$\ds \int_0^\pi \paren {P y_n'^2 + Q y_n^2} \rd x \le M$ :$\ds \int_0^\pi Py_n'^2 \rd x \le M + \size {\int_0^\pi Q y_n^2 \rd x} \le M + \max \limits_{a \mathop \le x \mathop \le b } \size {\map Q x} = M_1$ :$\ds \int_0^\pi \map {y_n'^2} x \rd x \le \dfrac {M_1} {\min \limits_{a \mathop \le x \mathop \le b} \map P x} = M_2$ :$\map {y_n} 0 = 0$ :$\ds \size {\map {y_n} x}^2 = \size {\int_0^x \map {y_n'} \zeta \rd \zeta}^2 \le \int_0^x \map {y_n'^2} \zeta \rd \zeta \int_0^x \rd \zeta \le M_2 \pi$ :$\ds \size {\map {y_n} {x_2} - \map {y_n} {x_1} }^2 = \size {\int_{x_1}^{x_2} \map {y_n'} x \rd x}^2 \le \int_{x_1}^{x_2} y_n'^2 \rd x \size {\int_{x_1}^{x_2} \rd x}^2 \le M_2 \size {x_2 - x_1}$ :$\map {y^{\paren 1} } x = \lim_{m \mathop \to \infty} \map {y_{n_m} } x$ :$\int_0^\pi \paren {-\paren {P h'}' + Q_1 h} y \rd x = 0$ :$\map h x \in \map {\DD_2} {0, \pi}$ :$\map h 0 = \map h \pi = \map {h'} 0 = \map {h'} \pi = 0$ :$\map y x \in \map {\DD_2} {0, \pi}$ :$-\paren {P y'}' + Q_1 y = 0$ :$\ds \int_0^\pi \paren {-\paren {P y'}' + Q_1 y} y \rd x = -\int_0^\pi P h'' y \rd x - \int_0^\pi P' h' y \rd x + \int_0^\pi Q_1 h y \rd x = - \int_0^\pi \paren {- P y + \int_0^x P' y \rd \zeta + \int_0^x \paren {\int_0^\zeta Q_1 y \rd t} \rd \zeta} \rd x = 0$ :$-\paren {P y}' + P' y + \ds \int_0^x Q_1 y \rd \zeta = c_1$ :$-P y' + \ds \int_0^x Q_1 y \rd \zeta = c_1$ :$-\paren {P y'}' + Q_1 y = 0$ :$-\paren {P {y^{\paren 1} }'}' + Q y^{\paren 1} = \lambda^{\paren 1} y^{\paren 1}$ :$\dfrac \partial {\partial \alpha_r} \paren {\map {J_n} {\alpha_1, \ldots, \alpha_n} - \lambda_n^{\paren 1} \ds \int_0^\pi \paren {\sum_{k \mathop = 1}^n \alpha_k \sin k x}^2 \rd x} = 0$ {{ProofWanted}} \end{proof}
21891
\section{Sturm-Liouville Problem/Unit Weight Function} Tags: Calculus of Variations \begin{theorem} Let $P, Q: \R \to \R$ be real mappings such that $P$ is smooth and positive, while $Q$ is continuous: :$\map P x \in C^\infty$ :$\map P x > 0$ :$\map Q x \in C^0$ Let the Sturm-Liouville equation, with $\map w x = 1$, be of the form: :$-\paren {P y'}' + Q y = \lambda y$ where $\lambda \in \R$. Let it satisfy the following boundary conditions: :$\map y a = \map y b = 0$ Then all solutions of the Sturm-Liouville equation, together with their eigenvalues, form infinite sequences $\sequence {y^{\paren n} }$ and $\sequence {\lambda^{\paren n} }$. Furthermore, each $\lambda^{\paren n}$ corresponds to an eigenfunction $y^{\paren n}$, unique up to a constant factor. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Suppose, $y^{\paren r}$ and $\lambda^{\paren r}$ are known. The next eigenfunction $y^{\paren {r + 1} }$ and the corresponding eigenvalue $\lambda^{\paren {r + 1} }$ can be found by minimising :$\ds J \sqbrk y = \int_0^\pi \paren {P y'^2 + Q y^2} \rd x $ where boundary and subsidiary conditions are supplied with orthogonality conditions: :$\forall m \in \N : {1 \le m \le r} : \ds \int_0^\pi \map {y^{\paren m} } t \map {y^{\paren {r + 1} } } t \rd t = 0$ The new solution of the form: :$\ds \map {y_n^{\paren {r + 1} } } t = \sum_{k \mathop = 1}^n \alpha_k^{\paren {r + 1} } \sin {k t}$ is now also orthogonal to mappings: :$\ds \map {y_n^{\paren m} } t = \sum_{k \mathop = 1}^n \alpha_k^{\paren m} \sin {k t}$ This results into: :$\ds \sum_{k \mathop = 1}^n \alpha_k^{\paren {r + 1} } \int_0^\pi \sin {k t} \paren {\sum_{l \mathop = 1}^n \alpha_l^{\paren m} \sin {l t} } \rd t = \frac \pi 2 \sum_{k \mathop = 1}^n \alpha_k^{\paren {r + 1} } \alpha_k^{\paren m} = 0$ These equations describe $r$ distinct $\paren {n - 1}$-dimensional hyperplanes, passing through the origin of coordinates in $n$ dimensions. These hyperplanes intersect the sphere $\sigma_n$, resulting in an $\paren {n - r}$-dimensional sphere $\hat \sigma_{n - r}$. By definition, it is a compact set. By Continuous Function on Compact Subspace of Euclidean Space is Bounded, $\map {J_n} {\boldsymbol \alpha}$ has a minimum on $\hat {\sigma}_{n - r}$. Denote it as $\lambda_n^{\paren {r + 1} }$. By Ritz Method implies Not Worse Approximation with Increased Number of Functions: :$\lambda_{n + 1}^{\paren {r + 1} } \le \lambda_n^{\paren {r + 1} }$ This, together with $J$ being bounded from below, implies: :$\ds \lambda^{\paren {r + 1} } = \lim_{n \mathop \to \infty} \lambda_n^{\paren {r + 1} }$ Additional constraints may or may not affect the new minimum: :$\lambda^{\paren r} \le \lambda^{\paren {r + 1} }$ Let: :$\ds \map {y_n^{\paren {r + 1} } } t = \sum_{k \mathop = 1}^n \alpha_k^{\paren {r + 1} } \sin {k t}$ $y^{\paren {r + 1} }$ satisfies Sturm-Liouville equation together with boundary, subsidiary and orthogonality conditions. By Lemma 7, which is not affected by additional constraints, $\sequence {y_n^{\paren {r + 1} } }$ uniformly converges to $y^{\paren {r + 1} }$. Thus, $y^{\paren {r + 1} }$ is an eigenfunction of Sturm-Liouville equation with an eigenvalue $\lambda^{\paren {r + 1} }$. Orthogonal mappings are linearly independent. Each eigenvalue corresponds only to one eigenfunction, unique up to a constant factor. Thus: :$\lambda^{\paren r} < \lambda^{\paren {r + 1} }$ {{qed}} \end{proof}
21892
\section{Sturm-Liouville Problem/Unit Weight Function/Lemma} Tags: Calculus of Variations \begin{theorem} Let $\map \alpha x: \R \to \R$ such that $\map \alpha x \in C^2 \closedint a b$. Suppose: :$\ds \forall \map h x \in C^2 \closedint a b: \map h a = \map h b = \map {h'} a = \map {h'} b = 0: \int_a^b \map \alpha x \, \map {h''} x \rd x = 0$ Then: :$\forall x \in \closedint a b: \map \alpha x = c_0 + c_1 x$ where $ c_0, c_1 \in \R $ are constants. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Let $ c_0, c_1$ be defined by the conditions: :$\ds \int_a^b \paren {\map \alpha x - c_0 - c_1 x} \rd x = 0$ :$\ds \int_a^b \rd x \int_a^x \paren {\map \alpha \xi - c_0 - c_1 \xi} \rd \xi = 0$ Suppose: :$\ds \map h x = \int_a^x \xi \int_a^\xi \paren {\map \alpha t - c_0 - c_1 t} \rd t$ This form satisfies conditions on $h$ in the theorem. Then: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = \int_a^b \paren {\map \alpha x - c_0 - c_1 x} \map {h''} x \rd x | r = \int_a^b \map \alpha x \map {h''} x \rd x - c_0 \paren {\map {h'} b - \map {h'} a} - c_1 \int_a^b x \map {h''} x \rd x }} {{eqn | r = -c_1 \paren {b \map {h'} b - a \map {h'} a} - c_1 \paren {\map h b - \map h a} }} {{eqn | r = 0 }} {{end-eqn}} On the other hand: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = \int_a^b \paren {\map \alpha x - c_0 - c_1 x} \map {h''} x \rd x | r = \int_a^b \paren {\map \alpha x - c_0 - c_1 x}^2 \rd x }} {{eqn | r = 0 }} {{end-eqn}} Therefore: :$\map \alpha x - c_0 - c_1 x = 0$ or: :$\map \alpha x = c_0 + c_1 x$ {{qed}} Category:Calculus of Variations \end{proof}
21893
\section{Sub-Basis for Real Number Line} Tags: Real Numbers, Topology, Topological Bases \begin{theorem} Let the real number line $\R$ be considered as a topology under the usual (Euclidean) topology. Then: :$\BB := \set {\openint \gets a, \openint b \to: a, b \in \R}$ is a sub-basis for $\R$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Let $\openint c d$ be an open real interval. Then by definition: :$\openint c d = \openint \gets d \cap \openint c \to$ and so $\openint c d$ is the intersection of two elements of $\BB$. From Open Sets in Real Number Line, any open set of $\R$ is the union of countably many open real intervals. The result follows by definition of sub-basis. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21894
\section{Sub-Basis for Topological Subspace} Tags: Topological Subspaces, Topological Bases \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {X, \tau}$ be a topological space. Let $K$ be a sub-basis for $\tau$. Let $\struct {S, \tau'}$ be a subspace of $\struct {X, \tau}$. Let $K' = \set {U \cap S: U \in K}$. That is, $K'$ consists of the $\tau'$-open sets in $S$ corresponding to elements of $K$. Then $K'$ is a sub-basis for $\tau'$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Let $B$ be the basis for $\tau$ generated by $K$. By Basis for Topological Subspace, $B$ generates a basis, $B'$, for $\tau'$. We will show that $K'$ generates $B'$. Let $V' \in B'$. Then for some $V \in B$: :$V' = S \cap V$ By the definition of a sub-basis, there is a finite subset $K_V$ of $K$ such that: :$\ds V = \bigcap K_V$ Let $K_V' = \set {S \cap U: U \in K_V}$. Then: :$\ds V' = S \cap V = S \cap \bigcap K_V$ so: :$\ds V' = \bigcap_{P \mathop \in K_V} \paren {S \cap P} = \bigcap K_V'$ Thus $B'$ is generated by $K'$. {{qed}} Category:Topological Bases Category:Topological Subspaces \end{proof}
21895
\section{Subalgebra of Algebraic Field Extension is Field} Tags: Integral Extensions, Integral Ring Extensions \begin{theorem} Let $E / F$ be an algebraic field extension. Let $A \subseteq E$ be a unital subalgebra over $F$. Then $A$ is a field. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} By Integral Ring Extension is Integral over Intermediate Ring, $E$ is integral over $A$. Let $a \in A$ be nonzero. Because $E$ is a field, $a$ is a unit of $E$. By Ring Element is Unit iff Unit in Integral Extension, $a$ is a unit of $A$. Thus $A$ is a field. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21896
\section{Subclass of Set is Set} Tags: Gödel-Bernays Class Theory \begin{theorem} Let $A$ be a set. Let $\map \phi x$ be a condition in which $x$ is taken to be a set. Then there exists a set that consists of all of the elements of $A$ that satisfies this condition. In ZF, this result is known as the Axiom of Specification. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} {{NotZFC}} By the axiom of class comprehension, let $B$ be the class defined as: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = B | r = \set {x: x \in A \land \map \phi x} }} {{eqn | r = \set {x \in A: \map \phi x} | c = Set-Builder Notation }} {{end-eqn}} {{AimForCont}} that $B$ is not a set. Then $B$ must be a proper class. It is easily seen that $B \subseteq A$. So by the Axiom of Powers: :$B \in \powerset A$ where $\powerset A$ is denotes the power set of $A$. But by Proper Class is not Element of Class, this is a contradiction. Therefore by contradiction it follows that $B$ is a set. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21897
\section{Subcover is Refinement of Cover} Tags: Covers \begin{theorem} Let $S$ be a set. Let $\CC$ be a cover for $S$. Let $\VV$ be a subcover of $\CC$. Then $\VV$ is a refinement of $\CC$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} From definition of subcover: :$\VV \subseteq \CC$ That is, every element of $\VV$ is an element of $\CC$. From definition of subset, every element of $\VV$ is the subset of some element of $\CC$. This is precisely the definition of refinement. {{qed}} Category:Covers \end{proof}
21898
\section{Subdomain Test} Tags: Rings, Integral Domains, Subrings \begin{theorem} Let $S$ be a subset of an integral domain $\struct {R, +, \circ}$. Then $\struct {S, + {\restriction_S}, \circ {\restriction_S} }$ is a subdomain of $\struct {R, +, \circ}$ {{iff}} these conditions hold: :$(1): \quad \struct {S, + {\restriction_S}, \circ {\restriction_S} }$ is a subring of $\struct {R, +, \circ}$ :$(2): \quad$ The unity of $R$ is also in $S$, that is $1_R = 1_S$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} By Idempotent Elements of Ring with No Proper Zero Divisors, it follows that the unity of a subdomain is the unity of the integral domain it's a subdomain of. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21899
\section{Subfield of Subfield is Subfield} Tags: Subfields \begin{theorem} Let $R$ be a ring with unity. Let $K_1, K_2$ be fields, such that: : $K_1$ is a subfield of $R$ : $K_2$ is a subfield of $K_1$ Then $K_2$ is a subfield of $R$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Let $K_1$ be a subfield of $R$ and $K_2$ be a subfield of $K_1$. Then by definition: :$K_1 \subseteq R$ :$K_2 \subseteq K_1$ From Subset Relation is Transitive it follows that $K_2 \subseteq R$ So by definition $K_2$ is a subfield of $R$. {{qed}} Category:Subfields \end{proof}
21900
\section{Subgroup Action is Group Action} Tags: Subgroup Action, Examples of Group Actions \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {G, \circ}$ be a group. Let $\struct {H, \circ}$ be a subgroup of $G$. Let $*: H \times G \to G$ be the subgroup action defined for all $h \in H, g \in G$ as: :$\forall h \in H, g \in G: h * g := h \circ g$ Then $*$ is a group action. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Let $g \in G$. First we note that since $G$ is closed, and $h \circ g \in G$, it follows that $h * g \in G$. Next we note: :$e * g = e \circ g = g$ and so {{GroupActionAxiom|2}} is satisfied. Now let $h_1, h_2 \in G$. We have: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = \paren {h_1 \circ h_2} * g | r = \paren {h_1 \circ h_2} \circ g | c = Definition of $*$ }} {{eqn | r = h_1 \circ \paren {h_2 \circ g} | c = {{GroupAxiom|1}} }} {{eqn | r = h_1 * \paren {h_2 * g} | c = Definition of $*$ }} {{end-eqn}} and so {{GroupActionAxiom|1}} is satisfied. Hence the result. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21901
\section{Subgroup Containing all Squares of Group Elements is Normal} Tags: Normal Subgroups \begin{theorem} Let $G$ be a group. Let $H$ be a subgroup of $G$ with the property that: :$\forall x \in G: x^2 \in H$ Then $H$ is normal in $G$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} We have: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = \paren {x h}^2 h^{-1} \paren {x^{-1} }^2 | r = x h x h h^{-1} x^{-1} x^{-1} | c = {{GroupAxiom|1}} }} {{eqn | r = x h x x^{-1} x^{-1} | c = {{GroupAxiom|3}} }} {{eqn | r = x h x^{-1} | c = {{GroupAxiom|3}} }} {{end-eqn}} Because $\paren {x h}^2$ and $\paren {x^{-1} }^2$ are in the form $x^2$ for $x \in G$, they are both elements of $H$. Thus: :$x h x^{-1} \in H$ and so $H$ is normal in $G$ by definition. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21902
\section{Subgroup Generated by Commuting Elements is Abelian} Tags: Abelian groups, Abelian Groups \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {G, \circ}$ be a group. Let $S \subseteq G$ such that: :$\forall x, y \in S: x \circ y = y \circ x$ Then the subgroup generated by $S$ is abelian. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Let $H = \gen S$ denote the subgroup generated by $S$. Let $a, b \in H$. Then: :$a = s_1$ :$b = s_2$ for some words $s_1, s_2$ of the set of words $\map W S$ of $S$. Then: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = a \circ b | r = s_1 \circ s_2 | c = }} {{eqn | r = s_2 \circ s_1 | c = as all elements of $S$ commute with each other }} {{eqn | r = b \circ a | c = }} {{end-eqn}} Hence the result, by definition of abelian group. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21903
\section{Subgroup Generated by Infinite Order Element is Infinite} Tags: Infinite Groups, Generated Subgroups, Order of Group Elements \begin{theorem} Let $G$ be a group. Let $a \in G$ be of infinite order. Let $\gen a$ be the subgroup generated by $a$. Then $\gen a$ is of infinite order. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} {{AimForCont}} $\gen a$ is of finite order. We have that $a \in \gen a$ by definition. From Element of Finite Group is of Finite Order it follows that $a$ is of finite order. From this contradiction it follows that $\gen a$ must be of infinite order after all. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21904
\section{Subgroup Generated by One Element is Cyclic} Tags: Generated Subgroups \begin{theorem} Let $G$ be a group. Let $a \in G$. Then $\gen a$, the subgroup generated by $a$, is cyclic: \end{theorem} \begin{proof} By Subgroup Generated by One Element is Set of Powers: :$\gen a = \set {a^n : n \in \Z}$ The result follows by definition of cyclic group. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21905
\section{Subgroup Generated by One Element is Set of Powers} Tags: Generated Subgroups, Subgroups \begin{theorem} Let $G$ be a group. Let $a \in G$. Then the subgroup generated by $a$ is the set of powers: :$\gen a = \set {a^n : n \in \Z}$ \end{theorem} \begin{proof} By definition, the subgroup generated by $a$ is the intersection of all subgroups containing $a$. By Powers of Element form Subgroup, the set $H = \set {a^n : n \in \Z}$ is a subgroup. Thus $\gen a \subseteq H$. By Power of Element in Subgroup, $H \subseteq \gen a$. By definition of set equality, $\gen a = H$. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21906
\section{Subgroup Generated by Subgroup} Tags: Generated Subgroups \begin{theorem} Let $G$ be a group. Let $H \le G$ be a subgroup of $G$. Then: :$H = \gen H$ where $\gen H$ denotes the subgroup generated by $H$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} By definition of generated subgroup, $\gen H$ is the smallest subgroup of $H$ containing $H$. Hence the result. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21907
\section{Subgroup Subset of Subgroup Product} Tags: Subset Products, Subgroups \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {G, \circ}$ be a group whose identity is $e$. Let $H$ and $K$ be subgroups of $G$. Then: :$H \subseteq H \circ K \supseteq K$ where $H \circ K$ denotes the subset product of $H$ and $K$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} By definition of subset product: :$H \circ K = \set {h \circ k: h \in H, k \in K}$ So: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l=x | o=\in | r=H | c= }} {{eqn | ll=\leadsto | l=x | r=x \circ e | c={{Defof|Identity Element}} }} {{eqn | o=\in | r=H \circ K | c=Identity of Subgroup }} {{eqn | ll=\leadsto | l=H | o=\subseteq | r=H \circ K | c={{Defof|Subset}} }} {{end-eqn}} and: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l=y | o=\in | r=K | c= }} {{eqn | ll=\leadsto | l=y | r=e \circ y | c={{Defof|Identity Element}} }} {{eqn | o=\in | r=H \circ K | c=Identity of Subgroup }} {{eqn | ll=\leadsto | l=K | o=\subseteq | r=H \circ K | c={{Defof|Subset}} }} {{end-eqn}} {{qed}} Category:Subset Products Category:Subgroups \end{proof}
21908
\section{Subgroup is Closed iff Quotient is Hausdorff} Tags: Hausdorff Spaces, Quotient Spaces, Topological Groups \begin{theorem} Let $G$ be a topological group. Let $H \le G$ be a subgroup. Let $G / H$ be their quotient. Then the following are equivalent: :$H$ is closed in $G$ :$G / H$ is Hausdorff \end{theorem} \begin{proof} {{ProofWanted|use Group Acts by Homeomorphisms Implies Projection on Quotient Space is Open and Open Projection and Closed Graph Implies Quotient is Hausdorff}} Category:Topological Groups Category:Hausdorff Spaces \end{proof}
21909
\section{Subgroup is Normal Subgroup of Normalizer} Tags: Normal Subgroups, Normalizers, Subgroups \begin{theorem} Let $G$ be a group. A subgroup $H \le G$ is a normal subgroup of its normalizer: :$H \le G \implies H \lhd \map {N_G} H$ \end{theorem} \begin{proof} From Subgroup is Subgroup of Normalizer we have that $H \le \map {N_G} H$. It remains to show that $H$ is normal in $\map {N_G} H$. Let $a \in H$ and $b \in \map {N_G} H$. By the definition of normalizer: :$b a b^{-1} \in H$ Thus $H$ is normal in $\map {N_G} H$. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21910
\section{Subgroup is Normal iff Contains Conjugate Elements} Tags: Conjugacy, Normal Subgroups \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {G, \circ}$ be a group whose identity is $e$. Let $N$ be a subgroup of $G$. Then $N$ is normal in $G$ {{iff}}: :$\forall g \in G: \paren {n \in N \iff g \circ n \circ g^{-1} \in N}$ :$\forall g \in G: \paren {n \in N \iff g^{-1} \circ n \circ g \in N}$ \end{theorem} \begin{proof} By definition, a subgroup is normal in $G$ {{iff}}: :$\forall g \in G: g \circ N = N \circ g$ \end{proof}
21911
\section{Subgroup is Subset of Conjugate iff Normal} Tags: Conjugacy, Normal Subgroups \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {G, \circ}$ be a group whose identity is $e$. Let $N$ be a subgroup of $G$. Then $N$ is normal in $G$ (by definition 1) {{iff}}: :$\forall g \in G: N \subseteq g \circ N \circ g^{-1}$ :$\forall g \in G: N \subseteq g^{-1} \circ N \circ g$ \end{theorem} \begin{proof} By definition, a subgroup is normal in $G$ {{iff}}: :$\forall g \in G: g \circ N = N \circ g$ First note that: :$(1): \quad \paren {\forall g \in G: N \subseteq g \circ N \circ g^{-1} } \iff \paren {\forall g \in G: N \subseteq g^{-1} \circ N \circ g}$ which is shown by, for example, setting $h := g^{-1}$ and substituting. \end{proof}
21912
\section{Subgroup is Superset of Conjugate iff Normal} Tags: Conjugacy, Normal Subgroups \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {G, \circ}$ be a group. Let $N$ be a subgroup of $G$. Then $N$ is normal in $G$ (by definition 1) {{iff}}: :$\forall g \in G: g \circ N \circ g^{-1} \subseteq N$ :$\forall g \in G: g^{-1} \circ N \circ g \subseteq N$ \end{theorem} \begin{proof} By definition, a subgroup is normal in $G$ {{iff}}: :$\forall g \in G: g \circ N = N \circ g$ First note that: :$(1): \quad \paren {\forall g \in G: g \circ N \circ g^{-1} \subseteq N} \iff \paren {\forall g \in G: g^{-1} \circ N \circ g \subseteq N}$ which is shown by, for example, setting $h := g^{-1}$ and substituting. \end{proof}
21913
\section{Subgroup of Abelian Group is Abelian} Tags: Abelian Groups, Subgroups, Group Theory \begin{theorem} A subgroup of an abelian group is itself abelian. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Follows directly from Restriction of Commutative Operation is Commutative. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21914
\section{Subgroup of Abelian Group is Normal} Tags: Abelian Groups, Normal Subgroups \begin{theorem} Every subgroup of an abelian group is normal. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Let $G$ be an abelian group. Let $H \le G$ be a subgroup of $G$. Then for all $a \in G$: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = y | o = \in | r = H^a | c = where $H^a$ is the conjugate of $H$ by $a$ }} {{eqn | ll= \leadstoandfrom | l = a y a^{-1} | o = \in | r = H | c = {{Defof|Conjugate of Group Subset}} }} {{eqn | ll= \leadstoandfrom | l = y | o = \in | r = H | c = because $a y a^{-1} = y$ as $G$ is abelian }} {{end-eqn}} {{Qed}} \end{proof}
21915
\section{Subgroup of Additive Group Modulo m is Ideal of Ring} Tags: Subgroups, Additive Group of Integers Modulo m, Additive Groups of Integers Modulo m, Modulo Addition, Ideal Theory, Modulo Arithmetic \begin{theorem} Let $m \in \Z: m > 1$. Let $\struct {\Z_m, +_m}$ be the additive group of integers modulo $m$. Then every subgroup of $\struct {\Z_m, +_m}$ is an ideal of the ring of integers modulo $m$ $\struct {\Z_m, +_m, \times_m}$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Let $H$ be a subgroup of $\struct {\Z_m, +_m}$ Suppose: : $(1): \quad h + \ideal m \in H$, where $\ideal m$ is a principal ideal of $\struct {\Z_m, +_m, \times_m}$ and : $(2): \quad n \in \N_{>0}$. Then by definition of multiplication on integers and Homomorphism of Powers as applied to integers: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = \paren {n + \ideal m} \times \paren {h + \ideal m} | r = \map {q_m} n \times \map {q_m} h | c = where $q_m$ is the quotient mapping }} {{eqn | r = \map {q_m} {n \times h} | c = }} {{eqn | r = \map {q_m} {n \cdot h} | c = }} {{eqn | r = n \cdot \map {q_m} h | c = }} {{end-eqn}} But: :$n \cdot \map {q_m} h \in \gen {\map {q_m} h}$ where $\gen {\map {q_m} h}$ is the group generated by $\map {q_m} h$. Hence by Epimorphism from Integers to Cyclic Group, $n \cdot \map {q_m} h \in H$. The result follows. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21916
\section{Subgroup of Additive Group of Integers Generated by Two Integers} Tags: Additive Group of Integer Multiples, Additive Groups of Integer Multiples \begin{theorem} Let $m, n \in \Z_{> 0}$ be (strictly) positive integers. Let $\struct {\Z, +}$ denote the additive group of integers. Let $\gen {m, n}$ be the subgroup of $\struct {\Z, +}$ generated by $m$ and $n$. Then: :$\gen {m, n} = \struct {\gcd \set {m, n} \Z, +}$ That is, the additive groups of integer multiples of $\gcd \set {m, n}$, where $\gcd \set {m, n}$ is the greatest common divisor of $m$ and $n$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} By definition: :$\gen {m, n} = \set {x \in \Z: \gcd \set {m, n} \divides x}$ {{Handwaving|Sorry, I would make the effort, but it's tedious.}} Hence the result. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21917
\section{Subgroup of Cyclic Group is Cyclic} Tags: Cyclic Groups, Subgroups, Subgroup of Cyclic Group is Cyclic, Group Theory \begin{theorem} Let $G$ be a cyclic group. Let $H$ be a subgroup of $G$. Then $H$ is cyclic. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Let <math>G</math> be a cyclic group generated by <math>a</math>. Let <math>H</math> be a subgroup of <math>G</math>. If <math>H = \left\{{e}\right\}</math>, then <math>H</math> is a cyclic subgroup generated by <math>e</math>. If <math>H \ne \left\{{e}\right\}</math>, then <math>a^n \in H</math> for some <math>n \in \Z</math> (since every element in <math>G</math> has the form <math>a^n</math> and <math>H</math> is a subgroup of <math>G</math>). Let <math>m</math> be the smallest positive integer such that <math>a^m \in H</math>. Consider an arbitrary element <math>b</math> of <math>H</math>. Since <math>H</math> is a subgroup of <math>G</math>, <math>b = a^n</math> for some <math>n</math>. Find integers <math>q</math> and <math>r</math> such that <math>n = mq + r</math> with <math>0 \leq r < m</math> by the Division Algorithm. It follows that <math>a^n = a^{mq + r} = \left({a^m}\right)^qa^r</math> and hence that <math>a^r = \left({a^m}\right)^{-q} a^n</math>. Since <math>a^m \in H</math> so is its inverse <math>\left({a^m}\right)^{-1}</math>, and all powers of its inverse by closure. Now <math>a^n</math> and <math>\left({a^m}\right)^{-q}</math> are both in <math>H</math>, thus so is their product <math>a^r</math> by closure. However, <math>m</math> was the smallest positive integer such that <math>a^m \in H</math> and <math>0 \leq r < m</math>, so <math>r = 0</math>. Therefore <math>n = q m</math> and <math>b = a^n = (a^m)^q</math>. We conclude that any arbitrary element <math>b = a^n</math> of <math>H</math> is generated by <math>a^m</math> so <math>H = \left \langle {a^m}\right \rangle </math> is cyclic. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21918
\section{Subgroup of Direct Product is not necessarily Direct Product of Subgroups} Tags: Group Direct Products \begin{theorem} Let $G$ and $H$ be groups. Let $G \times H$ denote the direct product of $G$ and $H$. Let $K$ be a subgroup of $G \times H$. Then it is not necessarily the case that $K$ is of the form: :$G' \times H'$ where: :$G'$ is a subgroup of $G$ :$H'$ is a subgroup of $H$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Let $G = H = C_2$, the cyclic group of order $2$. Let $G = \gen x$ and $H = \gen y$, so that: :$G = \set {e_G, x}$ :$H = \set {e_H, y}$ where $e_G$ and $e_H$ are the identity elements of $G$ and $H$ respectively. Consider the element $\tuple {x, y} \in G \times H$. We have that: :$\gen {\tuple {x, y} } =\set {\tuple {e_G, e_H}, \tuple {x, y} }$ but this is not the direct product of a subgroup of $G$ with a subgroup of $H$. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21919
\section{Subgroup of Elements whose Order Divides Integer} Tags: Abelian Groups \begin{theorem} Let $A$ be an abelian group. Let $k \in \Z$ and $B$ be a set of the form: :$\left\{{x \in A : x^k = e}\right\}$ Then $B$ is a subgroup of $A$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} First note that the identity $e$ satisfies $e^k = e$ and so $B$ is non-empty. Now assume that $a, b \in B$. Then: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l=\left({ab^{-1} }\right)^k | r=a^k \left({b^{-1} }\right)^k | c=Power of Product in Abelian Group }} {{eqn | r=a^k \left({b^k}\right)^{-1} | c=Powers of Group Elements }} {{eqn | r=ee^{-1} | c=as $a^k = b^k = e \in B$ }} {{eqn | r=e | c=Identity is Self-Inverse }} {{end-eqn}} Hence, by the One-Step Subgroup Test, $B$ is a subgroup of $A$. {{qed}} Category:Abelian Groups \end{proof}
21920
\section{Subgroup of Finite Cyclic Group is Determined by Order} Tags: Cyclic Group, Cyclic Groups \begin{theorem} Let $G = \gen g$ be a cyclic group whose order is $n$ and whose identity is $e$. Let $d \divides n$, where $\divides$ denotes divisibility. Then there exists exactly one subgroup $G_d = \gen {g^{n / d} }$ of $G$ with $d$ elements. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Let $G$ be generated by $g$, such that $\order g = n$. From Number of Powers of Cyclic Group Element, $g^{n/d}$ has $d$ distinct powers. Thus $\gen {g^{n / d} }$ has $d$ elements. Now suppose $H$ is another subgroup of $G$ of order $d$. Then by Subgroup of Cyclic Group is Cyclic, $H$ is cyclic. Let $H = \gen y$ where $y \in G$. Thus $\order y = d$. Thus $\exists r \in \Z: y = g^r$. Since $\order y = d$, it follows that $y^d = g^{r d} = e$. From Equal Powers of Finite Order Element: : $n \divides r d$ Thus: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | q = \exists k \in \N | l = k n | r = r d | c = }} {{eqn | r = k \paren {\dfrac n d} d | c = }} {{eqn | ll= \leadsto | l = r | r = k \paren {\dfrac n d} | c = }} {{eqn | ll= \leadsto | l = \dfrac n d | o = \divides | r = r | c = }} {{end-eqn}} Thus $y$ is a power of $g^{n / d}$. Hence $H$ is a subgroup of $\gen {g^{n / d} }$. Since both $H$ and $\gen {g^{n / d} }$ have order $d$, they must be equal. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21921
\section{Subgroup of Index 2 contains all Squares of Group Elements} Tags: Subgroups \begin{theorem} Let $G$ be a group. Let $H$ be a subgroup of $G$ whose index is $2$. Then: :$\forall x \in G: x^2 \in H$ \end{theorem} \begin{proof} By Subgroup of Index 2 is Normal, $H$ is normal in $G$. Hence the quotient group $G / H$ exists. Then we have: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | q = \forall x \in G | l = \paren {x^2} H | r = \paren {x H}^2 | c = }} {{eqn | r = H | c = as $G / H$ is of order $2$ }} {{end-eqn}} {{qed}} \end{proof}
21922
\section{Subgroup of Index 2 is Normal} Tags: Normal Subgroups \begin{theorem} A subgroup of index $2$ is always normal. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Suppose $H \le G$ such that $\index G H = 2$. Thus $H$ has two left cosets (and two right cosets) in $G$. If $g \in H$, then $g H = H = H g$. If $g \notin H$, then $g H = G \setminus H$ as there are only two cosets and the cosets partition $G$. For the same reason, $g \notin H \implies H g = G \setminus H$. That is, $g H = H g$. The result follows from the definition of normal subgroup. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21923
\section{Subgroup of Index 3 does not necessarily contain all Cubes of Group Elements} Tags: Subgroups \begin{theorem} Let $G$ be a group. Let $H$ be a subgroup of $G$ whose index is $3$. Then it is not necessarily the case that: :$\forall x \in G: x^3 \in H$ \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Proof by Counterexample: Consider $S_3$, the symmetric group on $3$ letters. From Subgroups of Symmetric Group on 3 Letters, the subgroups of $S_3$ are: subsets of $S_3$ which form subgroups of $S_3$ are: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | o = | r = S_3 }} {{eqn | o = | r = \set e }} {{eqn | o = | r = \set {e, \tuple {123}, \tuple {132} } }} {{eqn | o = | r = \set {e, \tuple {12} } }} {{eqn | o = | r = \set {e, \tuple {13} } }} {{eqn | o = | r = \set {e, \tuple {23} } }} {{end-eqn}} One such subgroup of $G$ whose index is $3$ is $\set {e, \tuple {12} }$ But $\set {e, \tuple {12} }$ does not contain $\tuple {123}$ or $\tuple {132}$, both of which are of order $3$. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21924
\section{Subgroup of Infinite Cyclic Group is Infinite Cyclic Group} Tags: Cyclic Groups, Subgroups \begin{theorem} Let $G = \gen a$ be an infinite cyclic group generated by $a$, whose identity is $e$. Let $g \in G, g \ne e: \exists k \in \Z, k \ne 0: g = a^k$. Let $H = \gen g$. Then $H \le G$ and $H \cong G$. Thus, all non-trivial subgroups of an infinite cyclic group are themselves infinite cyclic groups. A subgroup of $G = \gen a$ is denoted as follows: :$n G := \gen {a^n}$ This notation is usually used in the context of $\struct {\Z, +}$, where $n \Z$ is (informally) understood as '''the set of integer multiples of $n$'''. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} The fact that $H \le G$ follows from the definition of subgroup generator. By Infinite Cyclic Group is Isomorphic to Integers: :$G \cong \struct {\Z, +}$ Now we show that $H$ is of infinite order. Suppose $\exists h \in H, h \ne e: \exists r \in \Z, r > 0: h^r = e$. But: :$h \in H \implies \exists s \in \Z, s > 0: h = g^s$ where $g = a^k$. Thus: :$e = h^r = \paren {g^s}^r = \paren {\paren {a^k}^s}^r = a^{k s r}$ and thus $a$ is of finite order. This would mean that $G$ was also of finite order. So $H$ must be of infinite order. From Subgroup of Cyclic Group is Cyclic, as $G$ is cyclic, then $H$ must also be cyclic. From Infinite Cyclic Group is Isomorphic to Integers: :$H \cong \struct {\Z, +}$ Therefore, as $G \cong \struct {\Z, +}$: :$H \cong G$ {{qed}} \end{proof}
21925
\section{Subgroup of Integers is Ideal} Tags: Subgroups, Ideals, Ideal Theory, Integers, Subrings \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {\Z, +}$ be the additive group of integers. Every subgroup of $\struct {\Z, +}$ is an ideal of the ring $\struct {\Z, +, \times}$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Let $H$ be a subgroup of $\struct {\Z, +}$. Let $n \in \Z, h \in H$. Then from the definition of cyclic group and Negative Index Law for Monoids: :$n h = n \cdot h \in \gen h \subseteq H$ The result follows. {{Qed}} \end{proof}
21926
\section{Subgroup of Order 1 is Trivial} Tags: Subgroups \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {G, \circ}$ be a group. Then $\struct {G, \circ}$ has exactly $1$ subgroup of order $1$: the trivial subgroup. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} From Trivial Subgroup is Subgroup, $\struct {\set e, \circ}$ is a subgroup of $\struct {G, \circ}$. Suppose $\struct {\set g, \circ}$ is a subgroup of $\struct {G, \circ}$. From Group is not Empty, $e \in \set g$. Thus it follows trivially that $\struct {\set g, \circ} = \struct {\set e, \circ}$. That is, $\struct {\set e, \circ}$ is the only subgroup of $\struct {G, \circ}$ of order $1$. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21927
\section{Subgroup of Order p in Group of Order 2p is Normal} Tags: Groups of Order 2 p \begin{theorem} Let $p$ be an odd prime. Let $G$ be a group of order $2 p$. Let $a \in G$ be of order $p$. Let $K = \gen a$ be the subgroup of $G$ generated by $a$. Then $K$ is normal in $G$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} The result Non-Abelian Order 2p Group has Order p Element demonstrates that such an element $a$ exists in $G$. By definition of generator of cyclic group, $K$ is the cyclic group $C_p$ of order $p$. By Lagrange's Theorem, the index of $K$ is: :$\index G K = \dfrac {\order G} {\order K} = \dfrac {2 p} p = 2$ The result follows from Subgroup of Index 2 is Normal. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21928
\section{Subgroup of Order p in Group of Order 2p is Normal/Corollary} Tags: Groups of Order 2 p \begin{theorem} Let $p$ be an odd prime. Let $G$ be a group of order $2 p$ whose identity element is $e$. Let $a \in G$ be of order $p$. Let $K = \gen a$ be the subgroup of $G$ generated by $a$. Let $G$ be non-abelian. Every element of $G \setminus K$ is of order $2$, and: :$\forall b \in G \setminus K: b a b^{-1} = a^{-1}$ \end{theorem} \begin{proof} By Lagrange's Theorem, the elements of $G \setminus K$ can be of order $1$, $2$, $p$ or $2 p$. $1$ is not possible because Identity is Only Group Element of Order 1. Then we have that $G$ is non-abelian. Hence from Cyclic Group is Abelian, $G$ is not cyclic. Thus $\order b \ne 2 p$. It remains to investigate $2$ and $p$. Let $b \in G \setminus K$. By Subgroup of Index 2 contains all Squares of Group Elements: :$b^2 \in K$ {{AimForCont}} $b$ has order $p$. Then by Intersection of Subgroups of Prime Order: :$K \cap \gen b = e$ which contradicts $b^2 \in K$. Thus by Proof by Contradiction $\order b \ne p$ Hence it must follow that $\order b = 2$. {{qed|lemma}} We have that: :$b a \in G \setminus K$ Thus: :$\paren {b a}^2 = e$ {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = b a | o = \in | r = G \setminus K | c = }} {{eqn | ll= \leadsto | l = \paren {b a}^2 | r = e | c = }} {{eqn | ll= \leadsto | l = b a b | r = \paren {b a}^2 a^{-1} | c = }} {{eqn | r = a^{-1} | c = }} {{eqn | ll= \leadsto | l = b a b^{-1} | r = a^{-1} | c = as $b = b^{-1}$ }} {{end-eqn}} {{qed}} \end{proof}
21929
\section{Subgroup of Real Numbers is Discrete or Dense} Tags: Group Theory, Real Numbers, Topological Groups \begin{theorem} Let $G$ be a subgroup of the additive group of real numbers. Then one of the following holds: :$G$ is dense in $\R$. :$G$ is discrete and there exists $a \in \R$ such that $G = a \Z$, that is, $G$ is cyclic. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} If $G$ is trivial, then $G$ is discrete and cyclic. Let $G$ be non-trivial. Because $x \in G \iff -x \in G$, $G$ has a strictly positive element. Thus $G \cap \R_{>0}$ is non-empty. We have that $G \cap \R_{>0}$ is bounded below by $0$. Hence, by the Continuum Property, $G \cap \R_{>0}$ admits an infimum. So, let $a = \map \inf {G \cap \R_{>0} }$. \end{proof}
21930
\section{Subgroup of Solvable Group is Solvable} Tags: Subgroups, Solvable Groups, Subgroup of Solvable Group is Solvable \begin{theorem} Let $G$ be a solvable group. Let $H$ be a subgroup of $G$. Then $H$ is solvable. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} {{tidy|much work to be done}} {{MissingLinks}} {{refactor|proof per page, and we also go back to the original proof and reinstate it}} We will provide two proofs here, for the two equivalent definitions of solvable groups. Firstly we, know that a group is solvable if and only if its derived series $D(G)=[G,G] \ , \ D^i(G)= [D^{i-1}(G),D^{i-1}(G)$ becomes trivial after finite iteration. Meaning $D^j(G) = \{1\}$ for some finite j. Now it is trivial that $D(H) \leq D(G)$ since H is smaller than G. Further since $D^i(H)$ is dominated by $D^i(G)$ it too has to become trivial after a finite amount of steps. {{qed}} A different proof using the more common definition of solvability: Let $H \leq G$ and $G$ be solvable with normal series $1 = G_0 \lhd G_1 \lhd \dots \lhd G_m = G$ such that $G_{i+1}/G_i$ is abelian for all i. Define $N_i= G_i \cap H$. These $N_i$ will form a normal series with abelian factors. Normality: Let $x \in N_i$ and $y \in N{i+1}$ then $yxy^{-1} \in N$, since N is a group, and $yxy^{-1} \in G_i$, since $G_i$ is normal in $G_{i+1}$. Hence $N_i$ is stable under conjugation and therefore normal. Abelian Factors: We have: :$\dfrac{N_{i+1}}{N_i} = \dfrac{N_{i+1}}{N_{i+1}\cap G_i} \cong \dfrac{N_{i+1}G_i}{G_i} \leq \dfrac{G_{i+1}}{G_i}$ so the quotient $\dfrac{N_{i+1}}{N_i}$ is isomorphic to a subgroup of the abelian group $\dfrac{G_{i+1}}{G_i}$, due to the Second Isomorphism Theorem for Groups, hence its abelian, proving the theorem. {{qed}} {{Proofread|grammar's all over the place for a start}} \end{proof}
21931
\section{Subgroup of Subgroup with Prime Index} Tags: Index of Subgroups \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {G, \circ}$ be a group. Let $H$ be a subgroup of $G$. Let $K$ be a subgroup of $H$. Let: :$\index G K = p$ where: :$p$ denotes a prime number :$\index G K$ denotes the index of $K$ in $G$. Then either: :$H = K$ or: :$H = G$ \end{theorem} \begin{proof} From the Tower Law for Subgroups: :$\index G K = \index G H \index H K$ As $\index G K = p$ is prime, either $\index G H = p$ or $\index H K = p$. Thus either $\index G H = 1$ or $\index H K = 1$. The result follows from Index is One iff Subgroup equals Group. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21932
\section{Subgroup of Subgroup with Prime Index/Corollary} Tags: Index of Subgroups \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {G, \circ}$ be a group. Let $H$ and $K$ be subgroups of $G$. Let $K \subsetneq H$. Let: :$\index G K = p$ where: :$p$ denotes a prime number :$\index G K$ denotes the index of $K$ in $G$. Then: :$H = G$ \end{theorem} \begin{proof} As $K \subsetneq H$ and $K$ is a subgroups of $G$, it follows that $K$ is a proper subgroup of $H$. That is, $K \ne H$ Hence from Subgroup of Subgroup with Prime Index: :$H = G$ {{qed}} \end{proof}
21933
\section{Subgroup of Symmetric Group that Fixes n} Tags: Symmetric Groups \begin{theorem} Let $S_n$ denote the symmetric group on $n$ letters. Let $H$ denote the subgroup of $S_n$ which consists of all $\pi \in S_n$ such that: :$\map \pi n = n$ Then: :$H = S_{n - 1}$ and the index of $H$ in $S_n$ is given by: :$\index {S_n} H = n$ \end{theorem} \begin{proof} We have that $S_{n - 1}$ is the symmetric group on $n - 1$ letters. Let $\pi \in S_{n - 1}$. Then $\pi$ is a permutation on $n - 1$ letters. Hence $\pi$ is also a permutation on $n$ letters which fixes $n$. So $S_{n - 1} \subseteq H$. Now let $\pi \in H$. Then $\pi$ is a permutation on $n$ letters which fixes $n$. That is, $\pi$ is a permutation on $n - 1$ letters. Thus $\pi \in S_{n - 1}$. So we have that $H = S_{n - 1}$. We also have that $S_{n - 1}$ is a group, and: :$\forall \rho \in S_{n - 1}: \rho \in S_n$ So $S_{n - 1}$ is a subset of $S_n$ which is a group. Hence $S_{n - 1}$ is a subgroup of $S_n$ by definition. Then we have: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = \index {S_n} {S_{n - 1} } | r = \dfrac {\order {S_n} } {\order {S_{n - 1} } } | c = {{Defof|Index of Subgroup}} }} {{eqn | r = \dfrac {n!} {\paren {n - 1}!} | c = Order of Symmetric Group }} {{eqn | r = \dfrac {n \paren {n - 1}!} {\paren {n - 1}!} | c = {{Defof|Factorial}} }} {{eqn | r = n | c = }} {{end-eqn}} {{qed}} \end{proof}
21934
\section{Subgroups of Additive Group of Integers} Tags: Subgroups, Additive Groups of Integer Multiples, Additive Group of Integers, Subgroups of Additive Group of Integers, Group Theory, Integers, Additive Group of Integer Multiples \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {\Z, +}$ be the additive group of integers. Let $n \Z$ be the additive group of integer multiples of $n$. Every non-trivial subgroup of $\struct {\Z, +}$ has the form $n \Z$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} First we note that, from Integer Multiples under Addition form Infinite Cyclic Group, $\struct {n \Z, +}$ is an infinite cyclic group. From Cyclic Group is Abelian, it follows that $\struct {n \Z, +}$ is an infinite abelian group. Let $H$ be a non-trivial subgroup of $\struct {\Z, +}$. Because $H$ is non-trivial: :$\exists m \in \Z: m \in H: m \ne 0$ Because $H$ is itself a group: :$-m \in H$ So either $m$ or $-m$ is positive and therefore in $\Z_{>0}$. Thus: :$H \cap \Z_{>0} \ne \O$ From the Well-Ordering Principle, $H \cap \Z_{>0}$ has a smallest element, which we can call $n$. It follows from Subgroup of Infinite Cyclic Group is Infinite Cyclic Group that: : $\forall a \in \Z: a n \in H$ Thus: : $n \Z \subseteq H$ {{AimForCont}}: :$\exists m \in \Z: m \in H \setminus n \Z$ Then $m \ne 0$, and also $-m \in H \setminus n \Z$. Assume $m > 0$, otherwise we consider $-m$. By the Division Theorem: :$m = q n + r$ If $r = 0$, then $m = q n \in n \Z$, so $0 \le r < n$. Now this means $r = m - q n \in H$ and $0 \le r < n$. This would mean $n$ was not the smallest element of $H \cap \Z$. Hence, by Proof by Contradiction, there can be no such $m \in H \setminus n \Z$. Thus: :$H \setminus n \Z = \O$ Thus from Set Difference with Superset is Empty Set: :$H \subseteq n \Z$ Thus we have $n \Z \subseteq H$ and $H \subseteq n \Z$. Hence: :$H = n \Z$ {{qed}} \end{proof}
21935
\section{Subgroups of Additive Group of Integers Modulo m} Tags: Additive Groups of Integers Modulo m, Additive Group of Integers Modulo m \begin{theorem} Let $n \in \Z_{> 0}$ be a (strictly) positive integer. Let $\struct {\Z_m, +_m}$ denote the additive group of integers modulo $m$. The subgroups of $\struct {\Z_m, +_m}$ are the additive groups of integers modulo $k$ where: :$k \divides m$ \end{theorem} \begin{proof} From Integers Modulo m under Addition form Cyclic Group, $\struct {\Z_m, +_m}$ is cyclic. Let $H$ be a subgroup of $\struct {\Z_m, +_m}$ From Subgroup of Cyclic Group is Cyclic, $H$ is of the form $\struct {\Z_k, +_k}$ for some $k \in \Z$. From Lagrange's Theorem, it follows that $k \divides m$. Hence the result. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21936
\section{Subgroups of Cartesian Product of Additive Group of Integers} Tags: Additive Group of Integers, Additive Group of Integer Multiples, Additive Groups of Integer Multiples \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {\Z, +}$ denote the additive group of integers. Let $m, n \in \Z_{> 0}$ be (strictly) positive integers. Let $\struct {\Z \times \Z, +}$ denote the Cartesian product of $\struct {\Z, +}$ with itself. The subgroups of $\struct {\Z \times \Z, +}$ are not all of the form: :$\struct {m \Z, +} \times \struct {n \Z, +}$ where $\struct {m \Z, +}$ denotes the additive group of integer multiples of $m$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Consider the map $\phi: \struct {m \Z, +} \times \struct {n \Z, +} \mapsto \struct {\Z, +} \times \struct {\Z, +}$ defined by: :$\forall c, d \in \Z: \map \phi {m c, n d} = \tuple {c, d}$ which is a group isomorphism. {{explain|Prove the above statement}} Hence, $\struct {m \Z, +} \times \struct {n \Z, +}$ is a free abelian group of rank $2$. Therefore, any subgroup generated by a singleton, for example, $\set {\tuple {x, 0}: x \in \Z}$ is a subgroup not in the form $\struct {m \Z, +} \times \struct {n \Z, +}$. {{refactor|Implement "singly generated" as a definition page in its own right and then link to it, hence keep this page clean}} {{qed}} \end{proof}
21937
\section{Subring Generated by Unity of Ring with Unity} Tags: Ideal Theory \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {R, +, \circ}$ be a ring with unity whose zero is $0_R$ and whose unity is $1_R$. Let the mapping $g: \Z \to R$ be defined as $\forall n \in \Z: \map g n = n 1_R$, where $n 1_R$ the $n$th power of $1_R$. Let $\ideal x$ be the principal ideal of $\struct {R, +, \circ}$ generated by $x$. Then $g$ is an epimorphism from $\Z$ onto the subring $S$ of $R$ generated by $1_R$. If $R$ has no proper zero divisors, then $g$ is the only nonzero homomorphism from $\Z$ into $R$. The kernel of $g$ is either: :$(1): \quad \ideal {0_R}$, in which case $g$ is an isomorphism from $\Z$ onto $S$ or: :$(2): \quad \ideal p$ for some prime $p$, in which case $S$ is isomorphic to the field $\Z_p$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} By the Index Law for Sum of Indices and Powers of Ring Elements, we have $\paren {n 1_R} \paren {m 1_R} = n \paren {m 1_R} = \paren {n m} 1_R$. Thus $g$ is an epimorphism from $\Z$ onto $S$. {{AimForCont}} $R$ has no proper zero divisors. By Kernel of Ring Epimorphism is Ideal, the kernel of $g$ is an ideal of $\Z$. By Ring of Integers is Principal Ideal Domain, the kernel of $g$ is $\ideal p$ for some $p \in \Z_{>0}$. By Kernel of Ring Epimorphism is Ideal (don't think this is the correct reference - check it), $S$ is isomorphic to $\Z_p$ and also has no proper zero divisors. So from Integral Domain of Prime Order is Field either $p = 0$ or $p$ is prime. Now we need to show that $g$ is unique. Let $h$ be a non-zero (ring) homomorphism from $\Z$ into $R$. As $\map h 1 = \map h {1^2} = \paren {\map h 1}^2$, either $\map h 1 = 1_R$ or $\map h 1 = 0_R$ by Idempotent Elements of Ring with No Proper Zero Divisors. But, by Homomorphism of Powers: Integers, $\forall n \in \Z: \map h n = \map h {n 1} = n \map h 1$ So if $\map h 1 = 0_R$, then $\forall n \in \Z: \map h n = n 0_R = 0_R$. Hence $h$ would be a zero homomorphism, which contradicts our stipulation that it is not. So $\map h 1 = 1_R$, and thus $\forall n \in \Z: \map h n = n 1 = \map g n$. {{qed}} {{Proofread}} \end{proof}
21938
\section{Subring Module is Module} Tags: Subring Module is Module, Module Theory, Subrings, Modules \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {R, +, \times}$ be a ring. Let $\struct {S, +_S, \times_S}$ be a subring of $R$. Let $\struct {G, +_G, \circ}_R$ be an $R$-module. Let $\circ_S$ be the restriction of $\circ$ to $S \times G$. Let $\struct {G, +_G, \circ_S}_S$ be subring module induced by $S$. Then $\struct {G, +_G, \circ_S}_S$ is an $S$-module. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} We have that: :$\forall a, b \in S: a +_S b = a + b$ :$\forall a, b \in S: a \times_S b = a \times b$ :$\forall a \in S: \forall x \in G = a \circ_S x = a \circ x$ as $+_S$, $\times_S$ and $\circ_S$ are restrictions. Let us verify the module axioms. \end{proof}
21939
\section{Subring Module is Module/Special Case} Tags: Subring Module is Module, Module Theory, Subrings \begin{theorem} Let $S$ be a subring of the ring $\struct {R, +, \circ}$. Let $\circ_S$ be the restriction of $\circ$ to $S \times R$. Then $\struct {R, +, \circ_S}_S$ is an $S$-module. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} From Ring is Module over Itself, it follows that: :$\struct {R, +, \circ}_R$ is an $R$-module. The result follows directly from Subring Module is Module. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21940
\section{Subring Module is Module/Special Case/Unitary Module} Tags: Subring Module is Module \begin{theorem} Let $S$ be a subring of the ring $\struct {R, +, \circ}$. Let $\circ_S$ be the restriction of $\circ$ to $S \times R$. Let $\struct {R, +, \circ}$ be a ring with unity such that $1_R$ is that unity. Let $1_R \in S$. Then $\struct {R, +, \circ_S}_S$ is a unitary $S$-module. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} From Subring Module is Module: Special Case, we have that $\struct {R, +, \circ_S}_S$ is an $S$-module. Then {{hypothesis}} $1_R$ is the unity of $\struct {S, +, \circ_S}$. Thus $\struct {S, +, \circ_S}$ is also a ring with unity. It follows from Ring with Unity is Module over Itself that $\struct {R, +, \circ_S}_S$ is a unitary module. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21941
\section{Subring Module is Module/Unitary} Tags: Subring Module is Module \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {R, +, \times}$ be a ring. Let $\struct {S, +_S, \times_S}$ be a subring of $R$. Let $\struct {G, +_G, \circ}_R$ be an $R$-module. Let $\circ_S$ be the restriction of $\circ$ to $S \times G$. Let $\struct {R, +, \times}$ be a ring with unity. Let $\struct {G, +_G, \circ}_R$ be a unitary $R$-module. Let $1_R \in S$. Then $\struct{G, +_G, \circ_S}_S$ is also unitary. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} From Subring Module is Module, we have that $\struct {G, +_G, \circ_S}_S$ is an $S$-module. It remains to be demonstrated that $\struct{G, +_G, \circ_S}_S$ is unitary. To show this, we must prove that: :$\forall x \in G: 1_R \circ_S x = x$ Since $1_R \in S$ by assumption, the product $1_R \circ_S x$ is defined. We now have: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = 1_R \circ_S x | r = 1_R \circ x }} {{eqn | r = x | c = {{Module-axiom|4}} on $\struct {G, +_G, \circ}_R$ }} {{end-eqn}} and the proof is complete. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21942
\section{Subring is not necessarily Ideal} Tags: Ideal Theory \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {R, +, \circ}$ be a ring. Let $\struct {S, +_S, \circ_S}$ be a subring of $R$. Then it is not necessarily the case that $S$ is also an ideal of $R$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Consider the field of real numbers $\struct {\R, +, \times}$. We have that a field is by definition a ring, hence so is $\struct {\R, +, \times}$. From Rational Numbers form Subfield of Real Numbers and Integers form Subdomain of Rationals, it follows that the integers $\struct {\Z, +, \times}$ are a subring of $\struct {\R, +, \times}$. Consider $1 \in \Z$, and consider $\dfrac 1 2 \in \R$. We have that $1 \times \dfrac 1 2 = \dfrac 1 2 \notin \Z$. From this counterexample it is seen that $\Z$ is not an ideal of $R$. Hence the result, again by Proof by Counterexample. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21943
\section{Subring of Integers is Ideal} Tags: Integers, Subrings, Ideal Theory \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {\Z, +}$ be the additive group of integers. Every subring of $\struct {\Z, +, \times}$ is an ideal of the ring $\struct {\Z, +, \times}$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Follows directly from: :Subrings of Integers are Sets of Integer Multiples and: :Subgroup of Integers is Ideal. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21944
\section{Subring of Non-Archimedean Division Ring} Tags: Normed Division Rings, Definitions: Norm Theory, Definitions: Division Rings \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {R, \norm {\, \cdot \,} }$ be a normed division ring with non-archimedean norm $\norm {\, \cdot \,}$. Let $\struct {S, \norm {\, \cdot \,}_S }$ be a normed division subring of $R$. Then: :$\norm {\, \cdot \,}_S$ is a non-archimedean norm. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} $\forall x, y \in S$: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = \norm {x + y}_S | r = \norm {x + y} | c = Definition of $\norm {\,\cdot\,}_S$ }} {{eqn | o = \le | r = \max \set {\norm x, \norm y} | c = $(\text N 4)$: Ultrametric Inequality }} {{eqn | r = \max \set {\norm x_S, \norm y_S} | c = Definition of $\norm {\, \cdot \,}_S$ }} {{end-eqn}} {{qed}} Category:Normed Division Rings \end{proof}
21945
\section{Subring of Polynomials over Integral Domain Contains that Domain} Tags: Subrings, Polynomial Theory \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {R, +, \circ}$ be a commutative ring. Let $\struct {D, +, \circ}$ be an integral subdomain of $R$. Let $x \in R$. Let $D \sqbrk x$ denote the ring of polynomials in $x$ over $D$. Then $D \sqbrk x$ contains $D$ as a subring and $x$ as an element. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} We have that $\ds \sum_{k \mathop = 0}^m a_k \circ x^k$ is a polynomial for all $m \in \Z_{\ge 0}$. Set $m = 0$: :$\ds \sum_{k \mathop = 0}^0 a_k \circ x^k = a_k \circ x^0 = a_k \circ 1_D = a_k$ Thus: :$\ds \forall a_k \in D: \sum_{k \mathop = 0}^0 a_k \circ x^k \in D$ It follows directly that $D$ is a subring of $D \sqbrk x$ by applying the Subring Test on elements of $D$. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21946
\section{Subrings of Integers are Sets of Integer Multiples} Tags: Subrings of Integers are Sets of Integer Multiples, Integers, Subrings \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {\Z, +, \times}$ be the integral domain of integers. The subrings of $\struct {\Z, +, \times}$ are the rings of integer multiples: :$\struct {n \Z, +, \times}$ where $n \in \Z: n \ge 0$. There are no other subrings of $\struct {\Z, +, \times}$ but these. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} From Integer Multiples form Commutative Ring, it is clear that $\struct {n \Z, +, \times}$ is a subring of $\struct {\Z, +, \times}$ when $n \ge 1$. We also note that when $n = 0$, we have: :$\struct {n \Z, +, \times} = \struct {0, +, \times}$ which is the null ring. When $n = 1$, we have: :$\struct {n \Z, +, \times} = \struct {\Z, +, \times}$ From Null Ring and Ring Itself Subrings, these extreme cases are also subrings of $\struct {\Z, +, \times}$. From Subgroups of Additive Group of Integers, the only additive subgroups of $\struct {\Z, +, \times}$ are $\struct {n \Z, +}$. So there can be no subrings of $\struct {\Z, +, \times}$ which do not have $\struct {n \Z, +}$ as their additive group. Hence the result. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21947
\section{Subrings of Integers are Sets of Integer Multiples/Examples/Even Integers} Tags: Subrings of Integers are Sets of Integer Multiples \begin{theorem} Let $2 \Z$ be the set of even integers. Then $\struct {2 \Z, +, \times}$ is a subring of $\struct {\Z, +, \times}$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} From Subrings of Integers are Sets of Integer Multiples, a ring of the form $\struct {n \Z, +, \times}$ is a subring of $\struct {\Z, +, \times}$ when $n \ge 1$. $\struct {2 \Z, +, \times}$ is such an example. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21948
\section{Subsemigroup Closure Test} Tags: Semigroups, Subsemigroups, Abstract Algebra \begin{theorem} To show that an algebraic structure $\struct {T, \circ}$ is a subsemigroup of a semigroup $\struct {S, \circ}$, we need to show only that: :$(1): \quad T \subseteq S$ :$(2): \quad \circ$ is a closed operation in $T$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} From Restriction of Associative Operation is Associative, if $\circ$ is associative on $\struct {S, \circ}$, then it will also be associative on $\struct {T, \circ}$. Thus we do not need to check for associativity in $\struct {T, \circ}$, as that has been inherited from its extension $\struct {S, \circ}$. So, once we have established that $T \subseteq S$, all we need to do is to check for $\circ$ to be a closed operation. {{Qed}} \end{proof}
21949
\section{Subsemigroup of Cancellable Mappings is Subgroup of Invertible Mappings} Tags: Examples of Subgroups, Cancellability, Examples of Subsemigroups, Inverse Mappings \begin{theorem} Let $S$ be a set. Let $S^S$ denote the set of mappings from $S$ to itself. Let $\CC \subseteq S^S$ denote the set of cancellable mappings on $S$. Let $\MM \subseteq S^S$ denote the set of invertible mappings on $S$. Then: :the subsemigroup $\struct {\CC, \circ}$ of $\struct {S^S, \circ}$ coincides with the subgroup $\struct {\MM, \circ}$ of $\struct {S^S, \circ}$ where $\circ$ denotes composition of mappings. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} From Set of Invertible Mappings forms Symmetric Group, we have that $\struct {\MM, \circ}$ is a group. Hence, by definition, $\struct {\MM, \circ}$ is a subgroup of $\struct {S^S, \circ}$. Recall from Bijection iff Left and Right Inverse that a mapping is invertible {{iff}} it is a bijection. By definition, a cancellable mapping is a mapping both left cancellable and right cancellable. From Injection iff Left Cancellable and Surjection iff Right Cancellable, a cancellable mapping is both an injection and a surjection. That is, a mapping is cancellable mapping {{iff}} it is a bijection. That is, $\struct {\CC, \circ}$ is exactly the same as $\struct {\MM, \circ}$. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21950
\section{Subsemigroup of Monoid is not necessarily Monoid} Tags: Subsemigroups, Monoids, Identity Elements \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {S, \circ}$ be a monoid whose identity is $e_S$. Let $\struct {T, \circ}$ be a subsemigroup of $\struct {S, \circ}$ Then it is not necessarily the case that $\struct {T, \circ}$ has an identity. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Consider the set of integers under multiplication $\struct {\Z, \times}$. From Integers under Multiplication form Monoid, $\struct {\Z, \times}$ is a monoid. Let $n \in \Z$ such that $n > 1$. Let $n \Z$ be the set of integer multiples of $n$: :$\set {x \in \Z: n \divides x}$ where $\divides$ denotes divisibility. From Integer Multiples under Multiplication form Semigroup, $\struct {n \Z, \times}$ is a semigroup which has no identity. By construction, $n \Z$ is a subset of $\Z$. Hence $\struct {n \Z, \times}$ is a subsemigroup of $\struct {\Z, \times}$ which has no identity. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21951
\section{Subsemigroup of Ordered Semigroup is Ordered} Tags: Ordered Semigroups \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {S, \circ, \preceq}$ be an ordered semigroup. Let $\struct {T, \circ_T}$ be a subsemigroup of $\struct {S, \circ}$. Then the ordered structure $\struct {T, \circ_T, \preceq_T}$ is also an ordered semigroup. In the above: :$\circ_T$ denotes the operation induced on $T$ by $\circ$ :$\preceq_T$ denotes the restriction of $\preceq$ to $T \times T$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} It is necessary to ascertain that $\struct {T, \circ {\restriction_T} }$ fulfils the ordered semigroup axioms: {{:Axiom:Ordered Semigroup Axioms}} In this context, we see that $\text {OS} 0$ and $\text {OS} 1$ are fulfilled a fortiori by dint of $\struct {T, \circ {\restriction_T} }$ being a subsemigroup of $\struct {S, \circ}$. We have that $\struct {S, \circ, \preceq}$ is an ordered semigroup. From Restriction of Ordering is Ordering, we have that $\preceq_T$ is an ordering. Hence: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | q = \forall a, b \in S | l = a \preceq b | o = \implies | r = \paren {a \circ c} \preceq \paren {b \circ c} | c = Ordered Semigroup Axiom $\text {OS} 2$ on $\struct {S, \circ, \preceq}$ }} {{eqn | ll= \leadsto | q = \forall a, b \in T | l = a \preceq_T b | o = \implies | r = \paren {a \circ_T c} \preceq_T \paren {b \circ_T c} | c = }} {{end-eqn}} and: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | q = \forall a, b \in S | l = a \preceq b | o = \implies | r = \paren {c \circ a} \preceq \paren {c \circ b} | c = Ordered Semigroup Axiom $\text {OS} 2$ on $\struct {S, \circ, \preceq}$ }} {{eqn | ll= \leadsto | q = \forall a, b \in T | l = a \preceq_T b | o = \implies | r = \paren {c \circ_T a} \preceq_T \paren {c \circ_T b} | c = }} {{end-eqn}} Hence $\preceq_T$ fulfils Ordered Semigroup Axiom $\text {OS} 2$ on $\struct {T, \circ_T, \preceq_T}$. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21952
\section{Subsequence Characterisation of Compact Linear Transformations} Tags: Compact Linear Transformations \begin{theorem} Let $\mathbb F \in \set {\R, \C}$. Let $\struct {X, \norm \cdot_X}$ and $\struct {Y, \norm \cdot_Y}$ be normed vector spaces over $\mathbb F$. Let $A : X \to Y$ be a linear transformation. Then $A$ is compact {{iff}}: :all bounded sequences $\sequence {x_n}$ in $X$ have a subsequence $\sequence {x_{n_j} }$ such that the sequence $\sequence {A x_{n_j} }$ converges. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Let $\operatorname {ball} X$ be the closed unit ball of $X$. \end{proof}
21953
\section{Subsequence is Equivalent to Cauchy Sequence} Tags: Cauchy Sequences, Normed Division Rings \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {R, \norm {\, \cdot \,} }$ be a normed division ring. Let $\sequence {x_n}$ be a Cauchy sequence in $R$. Let $\sequence {x_{m_n} }$ be a subsequence of $\sequence {x_n}$. Then: :$\ds \lim_{n \mathop \to \infty} {x_n - x_{m_n} } = 0$ \end{theorem} \begin{proof} From Subsequence of Cauchy Sequence in Normed Division Ring is Cauchy Sequence: :$\sequence {x_{m_n} }$ is a Cauchy sequence Let $\epsilon > 0$. By definition of a Cauchy sequence: :$\exists N: \forall n, m > N: \norm {x_n - x_m } < \epsilon$ From Index of Subsequence not Less than its Index: $\forall n \in \N : m_n \ge n$ Thus: :$\exists N: \forall n > N: \norm {x_n - x_{m_n} } < \epsilon$ By definition of convergence: :$\ds \lim_{n \mathop \to \infty} {x_n - x_{m_n} } = 0$ {{qed}} Category:Cauchy Sequences Category:Normed Division Rings \end{proof}
21954
\section{Subsequence of Cauchy Sequence in Normed Division Ring is Cauchy Sequence} Tags: Cauchy Sequences, Normed Division Rings \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {R, \norm {\, \cdot \,} }$ be a normed division ring with zero: $0$. Let $\sequence {x_n}$ be a Cauchy sequence in $R$. Let $\sequence {x_{n_r} }$ be a subsequence of $\sequence {x_n}$. Then: :$\sequence {x_{n_r} }$ is a Cauchy sequence in $R$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Let $\epsilon > 0$. Since $\sequence {x_n}$ is a Cauchy sequence then: :$\exists N: \forall n,m > N: \norm {x_n - x_m } < \epsilon$ Now let $R = N$. Then from Strictly Increasing Sequence of Natural Numbers: :$\forall r, s > R: n_r \ge r$ and $n_s \ge s$ Thus $n_r, n_s > N$ and so: :$\norm {x_{n_r} - x_{n_s} } < \epsilon$ The result follows. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21955
\section{Subsequence of Real Sequence Diverging to Negative Infinity Diverges to Negative Infinity} Tags: Divergent Sequences, Limits of Sequences \begin{theorem} Let $\sequence {x_n}_{n \mathop \in \N}$ be a real sequence with $x_n \to -\infty$. Let $\sequence {x_{n_j} }_{j \mathop \in \N}$ be a subsequence of $\sequence {x_n}_{n \mathop \in \N}$. Then: :$x_{n_j} \to -\infty$ \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Let $M > 0$ be a real number. From the definition of divergence to $-\infty$, there exists $N \in \N$ such that: :$x_n < -M$ for each $n \ge N$. From Strictly Increasing Sequence of Natural Numbers, we have: :$n_j \ge j$ for each $j$. So, we have: :$x_{n_j} < -M$ for each $j \ge N$. Since $M$ was arbitrary, we have: :$x_{n_j} \to -\infty$ by the definition of divergence to $-\infty$. {{qed}} Category:Divergent Sequences Category:Limits of Sequences \end{proof}
21956
\section{Subsequence of Real Sequence Diverging to Positive Infinity Diverges to Positive Infinity} Tags: Divergent Sequences, Limits of Sequences \begin{theorem} Let $\sequence {x_n}_{n \mathop \in \N}$ be a real sequence with $x_n \to +\infty$. Let $\sequence {x_{n_j} }_{j \mathop \in \N}$ be a subsequence of $\sequence {x_n}_{n \mathop \in \N}$. Then: :$x_{n_j} \to +\infty$ \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Let $M > 0$ be a real number. From the definition of divergence to $+\infty$, there exists $N \in \N$ such that: :$x_n > M$ for each $n \ge N$. From Strictly Increasing Sequence of Natural Numbers, we have: :$n_j \ge j$ for each $j$. So, we have: :$x_{n_j} > M$ for each $j \ge N$. Since $M$ was arbitrary, we have: :$x_{n_j} \to \infty$ by the definition of divergence to $+\infty$. {{qed}} Category:Divergent Sequences Category:Limits of Sequences \end{proof}
21957
\section{Subsequence of Sequence in Metric Space with Limit} Tags: Metric Spaces, Limits of Sequences \begin{theorem} Let $M = \struct {A, d}$ be a metric space. Let $\sequence {x_n}$ be a sequence in $M$. Let $x$ be a limit point of $S = \set {x_n: n \in \N}$, the set of members of $\sequence {x_n}$. Then $\sequence {x_n}$ has a subsequence which converges to $x$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} By Finite Subset of Metric Space has no Limit Points, $S$ is infinite (or it has no limit points). We may assume that $x_n$ never equals $x$. Otherwise we delete all instances of $x$ from $\sequence {x_n}$ and create a new sequence $x_m$ which is a subsequence of $x_n$ which ''does'' never equal $x$. Then $S \setminus \set x$ is still infinite, and it still has $x$ as a limit point. So, since $x$ is a limit point of $S$, there is an integer $\map n 1$, say, such that $x_{\map n 1} \in \map {B_1} x$, where $\map {B_1} x$ is the open $1$-ball of $x$. Suppose we choose the integers $\map n 1 < \map n 2 < \cdots < \map n k$ so that $x_{\map n i} \in \map {B_{1/i} } x$ for $i = 1, 2, \ldots, k$. Now we put $\epsilon = \min \set {\dfrac 1 {k+1}, \map d {x_1, x}, \map d {x_2, x}, \map d {x_{\map n k}, x} }$. Since $x_n \ne x$ for any $n$, it follows that $\epsilon > 0$. Since $x$ is a limit point of $S$, there exists an integer $\map n {k+1}$ such that $x_{\map n {k+1} } \in \map {B_\epsilon} x$. Now $\epsilon$ has been chosen so as to force $\map n {k+1} > \map n k$, since $\map d {x_i, x} \ge \epsilon$ for all $i \le \map n k$. Also, note that $x_{\map n {k+1} } \in \map {B_{\frac 1 {k+1}} } x$. This completes the inductive step in constructing a subsequence. This converges to $x$, because $\forall k_0 \in \N_{>0}$ and $\forall k \ge k_0$ we have $\map d {x_{\map n k}, x} < \dfrac 1 k \ge \dfrac 1 {k_0}$. Hence the result. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21958
\section{Subsequence of Subsequence} Tags: Subsequences \begin{theorem} Let $s$ be a set. Let $\sequence {s_n}$ be a sequence in $S$. Let $\sequence {s_m}$ be a subsequence of $\sequence {s_n}$. Let $\sequence {s_k}$ be a subsequence of $\sequence {s_m}$. Then $\sequence {s_k}$ is a subsequence of $\sequence {s_n}$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} By definition, there exists a strictly increasing sequence $\sequence {n_r}$ in $\N$ such that: :$\forall m \in \N: s_m = s_{n_r}$ Similarly, there exists a strictly increasing sequence $\sequence {m_s}$ in $\N$ such that: :$\forall k \in \N: s_k = s_{m_s}$ We have that: :$\forall k \in \N: s_k \in \sequence {s_m}$ and that: :$\forall m \in \N: s_m \in \sequence {s_n}$ hence: :$\forall k \in \N: s_k \in \sequence {s_n}$ Because $\sequence {s_k}$ is a subsequence of $\sequence {s_m}$, we have that: :$k = m_s \implies k + 1 = m_s + p$ for some $p \in \Z_{>0}$ and: :$m_s = n_r \implies m_s + p = n_r + q$ for some $q \in \Z_{>0}$ Hence: :$k = n_r \implies k + 1 = n_r + q$ and so $\sequence {s_k}$ is a subsequence of $\sequence {s_n}$. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21959
\section{Subset Equivalences} Tags: Set Theory, Set Complement, Intersection, Empty Set, Subsets, Universe, Union, Subset, Set Difference \begin{theorem} These statements concerning subsets are equivalent: * <math>S \subseteq T</math> * <math>S \cup T = T</math> * <math>S \cap T = S</math> * <math>S \setminus T = \varnothing</math> * <math>S \cap \complement \left({T}\right) = \varnothing</math> * <math>\complement \left({S}\right) \cup T = \mathbb{U}</math> * <math>\complement \left({T}\right) \subseteq \complement \left({S}\right)</math> where: * <math>S \subseteq T</math> denotes that <math>S</math> is a subset of <math>T</math>; * <math>S \cup T</math> denotes the union of <math>S</math> and <math>T</math>; * <math>S \cap T</math> denotes the intersection of <math>S</math> and <math>T</math>; * <math>S \setminus T</math> denotes the set difference between <math>S</math> and <math>T</math>; * <math>\varnothing</math> denotes the empty set; * <math>\complement</math> denotes the complement of <math>S</math>; * <math>\mathbb{U}</math> denotes the universal set. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} * Let <math>S \cup T = T</math>. Then from the definition of set equality, <math>S \cup T \subseteq T</math>. Thus: {{begin-equation}} {{equation | l=<math>S</math> | o=<math>\subseteq</math> | r=<math>S \cup T</math> | c=Subset of Union }} {{equation | ll=<math>\implies</math> | l=<math>S</math> | o=<math>\subseteq</math> | r=<math>T</math> | c=Subsets Transitive }} {{end-equation}} * Now let <math>S \subseteq T</math>. We have: {{begin-equation}} {{equation | l=<math>S</math> | o=<math>\subseteq</math> | r=<math>T</math> | c= }} {{equation | ll=<math>\implies</math> | l=<math>S \cup T</math> | o=<math>\subseteq</math> | r=<math>T \cup T</math> | c=Set Union Preserves Subsets }} {{equation | ll=<math>\implies</math> | l=<math>S \cup T</math> | o=<math>\subseteq</math> | r=<math>T</math> | c=Union is Idempotent }} {{end-equation}} Alternatively: {{begin-equation}} {{equation | l=<math>T</math> | o=<math>\subseteq</math> | r=<math>T</math> | c=Subset of Itself }} {{equation | ll=<math>\implies</math> | l=<math>S \subseteq T</math> | o=<math>\and</math> | r=<math>T \subseteq T</math> | c=Rule of Conjunction }} {{equation | ll=<math>\implies</math> | l=<math>S \cup T</math> | o=<math>\subseteq</math> | r=<math>T</math> | c=Union Smallest }} {{end-equation}} From Subset of Union, we have <math>T \subseteq S \cup T</math>. So we have <math>T \subseteq S \cup T \and S \cup T \subseteq T</math>. Hence by the definition of set equality, <math>S \cup T = T</math>. Thus <math>S \subseteq T \implies S \cup T = T</math>. Hence <math>S \subseteq T \iff S \cup T = T</math>, so <math>S \cup T = T</math> and <math>S \subseteq T</math> are equivalent. {{Qed}} ---- * Let <math>S \cap T = S</math>. Then by the definition of set equality, <math>S \subseteq S \cap T</math>. Thus: {{begin-equation}} {{equation | l=<math>S \cap T</math> | o=<math>\subseteq</math> | r=<math>T</math> | c=Intersection Subset }} {{equation | ll=<math>\implies</math> | l=<math>S</math> | o=<math>\subseteq</math> | r=<math>T</math> | c=Subsets Transitive }} {{end-equation}} * Now let <math>S \subseteq T</math>. We have: {{begin-equation}} {{equation | l=<math>S</math> | o=<math>\subseteq</math> | r=<math>T</math> | c= }} {{equation | ll=<math>\implies</math> | l=<math>S \cap S</math> | o=<math>\subseteq</math> | r=<math>T \cap S</math> | c=Set Intersection Preserves Subsets }} {{equation | ll=<math>\implies</math> | l=<math>S</math> | o=<math>\subseteq</math> | r=<math>S \cap T</math> | c=Intersection is Idempotent and Intersection is Commutative }} {{end-equation}} Alternatively: {{begin-equation}} {{equation | l=<math>S</math> | o=<math>\subseteq</math> | r=<math>S</math> | c=Subset of Itself }} {{equation | ll=<math>\implies</math> | l=<math>S \subseteq S</math> | o=<math>\and</math> | r=<math>S \subseteq T</math> | c=Rule of Conjunction }} {{equation | ll=<math>\implies</math> | l=<math>S</math> | o=<math>\subseteq</math> | r=<math>S \cap T</math> | c=Intersection Largest }} {{end-equation}} Then we have: {{begin-equation}} {{equation | l=<math>S \cap T</math> | o=<math>\subseteq</math> | r=<math>S</math> | c=Intersection Subset }} {{equation | ll=<math>\implies</math> | l=<math>S \cap T</math> | o=<math>=</math> | r=<math>S</math> | c=Set Equality }} {{end-equation}} So we have <math>S \cap T = S \implies S \subseteq T</math> and <math>S \subseteq T \implies S \cap T = S</math> and so: :<math>S \subseteq T \iff S \cap T = S</math>. {{Qed}} ---- {{begin-equation}} {{equation | l=<math>S \setminus T = \varnothing</math> | o=<math>\iff</math> | r=<math>\neg \left({\exists x: x \in S \and x \notin T}\right)</math> | c=Definition of Empty Set }} {{equation | o=<math>\iff</math> | r=<math>\forall x: \neg \left({x \in S \and x \notin T}\right)</math> | c=De Morgan's Laws (Predicate Logic) }} {{equation | o=<math>\iff</math> | r=<math>\forall x: x \notin S \or x \in T</math> | c=De Morgan's Laws }} {{equation | o=<math>\iff</math> | r=<math>\forall x: x \in S \implies x \in T</math> | c=Material Implication }} {{equation | o=<math>\iff</math> | r=<math>S \subseteq T</math> | c=Definition of Subset }} {{end-equation}} Thus <math>S \subseteq T \iff S \setminus T = \varnothing</math>. {{qed}} ---- {{begin-equation}} {{equation | l=<math>S \subseteq T</math> | o=<math>\iff</math> | r=<math>S \setminus T = \varnothing</math> | c=from above }} {{equation | o=<math>\iff</math> | r=<math>S \cap \complement \left({T}\right) = \varnothing</math> | c=Set Difference as Intersection with Complement }} {{end-equation}} Thus <math>S \subseteq T \iff S \cap \complement \left({T}\right) = \varnothing</math>. {{qed}} ---- {{begin-equation}} {{equation | l=<math>S \subseteq T</math> | o=<math>\iff</math> | r=<math>S \cap \complement \left({T}\right) = \varnothing</math> | c=from above }} {{equation | o=<math>\iff</math> | r=<math>\complement \left({S \cap \complement \left({T}\right)}\right) = \mathbb{U}</math> | c=Complement of Null }} {{equation | o=<math>\iff</math> | r=<math>\complement \left({S}\right) \cup \complement \left({\complement \left({T}\right)}\right) = \mathbb{U}</math> | c=De Morgan's Laws }} {{equation | o=<math>\iff</math> | r=<math>\complement \left({S}\right) \cup T = \mathbb{U}</math> | c=Complement of Complement }} {{end-equation}} Thus <math>S \subseteq T \iff \complement \left({S}\right) \cup T = \mathbb{U}</math> {{qed}} ---- {{begin-equation}} {{equation | l=<math>S \subseteq T</math> | o=<math>\iff</math> | r=<math>\left({x \in S \implies x \in T}\right)</math> | c=Definition of Subset }} {{equation | o=<math>\iff</math> | r=<math>\left({x \notin T \implies x \notin S}\right)</math> | c=Rule of Transposition }} {{equation | o=<math>\iff</math> | r=<math>\left({x \in \complement \left({T}\right) \implies x \in \complement \left({S}\right)}\right)</math> | c=Definition of Complement }} {{equation | o=<math>\iff</math> | r=<math>\complement \left({T}\right) \subseteq \complement \left({S}\right)</math> | c=Definition of Subset }} {{end-equation}} Thus <math>S \subseteq T \iff \complement \left({T}\right) \subseteq \complement \left({S}\right)</math>. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21960
\section{Subset Product Action is Group Action} Tags: Subset Products, Cosets, Group Actions, Subset Product Action \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {G, \circ}$ be a group whose identity is $e$. Let $\powerset G$ be the power set of $\struct {G, \circ}$. For any $S \in \powerset G$ and for any $g \in G$, the subset product action: :$\forall g \in G: \forall S \in \powerset G: g * S = g \circ S$ is a group action. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Let $g \in G$. First we note that since $G$ is closed, and $g \circ S$ consists of products of elements of $G$, it follows that: :$g * S \subseteq G$ Next we note: :$e * S = e \circ S = \set {e \circ s: s \in S} = \set {s: s \in S} = S$ and so {{GroupActionAxiom|2}} is satisfied. Now let $g, h \in G$. We have: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = \paren {g \circ h} * S | r = \paren {g \circ h} \circ S | c = }} {{eqn | r = \set {\paren {g \circ h} \circ s: s \in S} | c = }} {{eqn | r = \set {g \circ \paren {h \circ s}: s \in S} | c = }} {{eqn | r = g * \set {h \circ s: s \in S} | c = }} {{eqn | r = g * \paren {h \circ S} | c = }} {{eqn | r = g * \paren {h * S} | c = }} {{end-eqn}} and so {{GroupActionAxiom|1}} is satisfied. Hence the result. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21961
\section{Subset Product defining Inverse Completion of Commutative Semigroup is Commutative Semigroup} Tags: Inverse Completions \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {S, \circ}$ be a commutative semigroup. Let $\struct {C, \circ} \subseteq \struct {S, \circ}$ be the subsemigroup of cancellable elements of $\struct {S, \circ}$. Let $\struct {T, \circ'}$ be an inverse completion of $\struct {S, \circ}$. Then: :$S \circ' C^{-1}$ is a commutative semigroup where $S \circ' C^{-1}$ is the subset product of $S$ with $C^{-1}$ under $\circ'$ in $T$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Note that by definition of inverse completion, $\struct {T, \circ'}$ is a semigroup. Thus $\circ'$ is associative. First it is demonstrated that $S \circ' C^{-1}$ is a semigroup. Let $x, z \in S$. Let $y, w \in C$. Then: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = \paren {x \circ' y^{-1} } \circ' \paren {z \circ' w^{-1} } | r = x \circ' \paren {y^{-1} \circ' z} \circ' w^{-1} | c = Associativity of $\circ'$ }} {{eqn | r = x \circ' \paren {z \circ' y^{-1} } \circ' w^{-1} | c = Commutation with Inverse in Monoid }} {{eqn | r = \paren {x \circ' z} \circ' \paren {y^{-1} \circ' w^{-1} } | c = Associativity of $\circ'$ }} {{eqn | r = \paren {x \circ' z} \circ' \paren {w \circ' y}^{-1} | c = Inverse of Product in Monoid }} {{eqn | r = \paren {x \circ z} \circ' \paren {w \circ y}^{-1} | c = $\circ'$ extends $\circ$ }} {{end-eqn}} Thus: :$\paren {x \circ z} \circ' \paren {w \circ y}^{-1} \in S \circ' C^{-1}$ proving that $S \circ' C^{-1}$ is closed. Therefore by Subsemigroup Closure Test: :$S \circ' C^{-1}$ is a subsemigroup of $\struct {T, \circ'}$ and thus a semigroup. {{qed|lemma}} It remains to be shown that $\circ'$ is a commutative operation. Let $\paren {x \circ' y^{-1} }$ and $\paren {z \circ' w^{-1} }$ be two arbitrary elements of $S \circ' C^{-1}$. By Element Commutes with Product of Commuting Elements, $x, y, z, w$ all commute with each other under $\circ$. As $\circ'$ is an extension of $\circ$, it follows that $x, y, z, w$ also all commute with each other under $\circ'$. Then: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = \paren {x \circ' y^{-1} } \circ' \paren {z \circ' w^{-1} } | r = x \circ' \paren {y^{-1} \circ' z} \circ' w^{-1} | c = Associativity of $\circ'$ }} {{eqn | r = x \circ' \paren {z \circ' y^{-1} } \circ' w^{-1} | c = Commutation with Inverse in Monoid }} {{eqn | r = \paren {x \circ' z} \circ' \paren {y^{-1} \circ' w^{-1} } | c = Associativity of $\circ'$ }} {{eqn | r = \paren {z \circ' x} \circ' \paren {w^{-1} \circ' y^{-1} } | c = Commutation of Inverses in Monoid }} {{eqn | r = z \circ' \paren {x \circ' w^{-1} } \circ' y^{-1} | c = Associativity of $\circ'$ }} {{eqn | r = z \circ' \paren {w^{-1} \circ' x} \circ' y^{-1} | c = Commutation with Inverse in Monoid }} {{eqn | r = \paren {z \circ' w^{-1} } \circ' \paren {x \circ' y^{-1} } | c = Associativity of $\circ'$ }} {{end-eqn}} So $x \circ' y^{-1}$ commutes with $z \circ' w^{-1}$. It follows by definition that $S \circ' C^{-1}$ is a commutative semigroup. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21962
\section{Subset Product is Subset of Generator} Tags: Subset Products, Group Theory \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {G, \circ}$ be a group. Let $X, Y \subseteq \struct {G, \circ}$. Then $X \circ Y \subseteq \gen {X, Y}$ where: :$X \circ Y$ is the Subset Product of $X$ and $Y$ in $G$. :$\gen {X, Y}$ is the subgroup of $G$ generated by $X$ and $Y$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} It is clear from Set of Words Generates Group that $\map W {\hat X \cup \hat Y} = \gen {X, Y}$. It is equally clear that $X \circ Y \subseteq \map W {\hat X \cup \hat Y}$. {{qed}} Category:Group Theory Category:Subset Products \end{proof}
21963
\section{Subset Product of Abelian Subgroups} Tags: Abelian Groups, Subset Products \begin{theorem} Let $\left({G, \circ}\right)$ be an abelian group. Let $H_1$ and $H_2$ be subgroups of $G$. Then $H_1 \circ H_2$ is a subgroup of $G$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} From Subgroup of Abelian Group is Normal, $H_1$ and $H_2$ are normal. The result follows from Subset Product with Normal Subgroup is Subgroup. {{qed}} Category:Abelian Groups Category:Subset Products \end{proof}
21964
\section{Subset Product of Normal Subgroups is Normal} Tags: Normal Subgroups, Subset Products \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {G, \circ}$ be a group. Let $N$ and $N'$ be normal subgroups of $G$. Then $N N'$ is also a normal subgroup of $G$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} From Subset Product with Normal Subgroup is Subgroup, we already have that $N N'$ is a subgroup of $G$. Let $n n' \in N N'$, so that $n \in N, n' \in N'$. Let $g \in G$. From Subgroup is Normal iff Contains Conjugate Elements: :$g n g^{-1}\in N, g n' g^{-1}\in N'$ So: :$\paren {g n g^{-1} } \paren {g n' g^{-1} } = g n n' g^{-1} \in N N'$ So $N N'$ is normal. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21965
\section{Subset Product of Normal Subgroups with Trivial Intersection} Tags: Group Direct Products, Normal Subgroups \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {G, \circ}$ be a group whose identity is $e$. Let $H, K$ be normal subgroups of $G$. Let $H \cap K = e$. Then $H K$ is isomorphic to $H \times K$ where: : $H K$ denotes the subset product of $H$ and $K$ : $H \times K$ denotes the direct product of $H$ and $K$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Let $G' = H K$. From Subset Product of Normal Subgroups is Normal, $G'$ is a normal subgroup of $G$. That is $G'$ is itself a group. So by the Internal Direct Product Theorem, $G'$ is the internal group direct product of $H$ and $K$. The result follows by definition of the internal group direct product. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21966
\section{Subset Product with Identity} Tags: Subset Products, Abstract Algebra \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {S, \circ}$ be a magma. Let $\struct {S, \circ}$ have an identity element $e$. Then $e \circ S = S \circ e = S$, where $\circ$ is understood to be the subset product with singleton. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = e \circ S | r = \set e \circ S | c = {{Defof|Subset Product with Singleton}} }} {{eqn | r = \set {x \circ y: x \in \set e, \, y \in S} | c = {{Defof|Subset Product}} }} {{eqn | r = \set {e \circ y: y \in S} | c = }} {{eqn | r = \set {y: y \in S} | c = {{Defof|Identity Element}} }} {{eqn | r = S | c = }} {{end-eqn}} Thus: :$e \circ S = S$ A similar argument shows that: :$S \circ e = S$ {{qed}} Category:Subset Products \end{proof}
21967
\section{Subset Product with Normal Subgroup as Generator} Tags: Normal Subgroups, Subset Products \begin{theorem} Let $G$ be a group whose identity is $e$. Let: :$H$ be a subgroup of $G$ :$N$ be a normal subgroup of $G$. Then: :$N \lhd \gen {N, H} = N H = H N \le G$ where: :$\le$ denotes subgroup :$\lhd$ denotes normal subgroup :$\gen {N, H}$ denotes a subgroup generator :$N H$ denotes subset product. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} From Subset Product is Subset of Generator: :$N H \subseteq \gen {N, H}$ From Subset Product with Normal Subgroup is Subgroup: :$N H = H N \le G$ Then by the definition of a subgroup generator, $\gen {N, H}$ is the smallest subgroup containing $N H$ and so: :$\gen {N, H} = N H = H N \le G$ From Normal Subgroup of Subset Product of Subgroups we have that: :$N \lhd N H$ Hence the result. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21968
\section{Subset Product with Normal Subgroup is Subgroup} Tags: Normal Subgroups, Subset Products \begin{theorem} Let $G$ be a group whose identity is $e$. Let: :$(1): \quad H$ be a subgroup of $G$ :$(2): \quad N$ be a normal subgroup of $G$. Let $H N$ denote subset product. Then $H N$ and $N H$ are both subgroups of $G$. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} It is clear that $e \in N H$, so $N H \ne \O$. Suppose $n_1, n_2 \in N$ and $h_1, h_2 \in H$. Then: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = \paren {n_1 h_1} \paren {n_2 h_2} | r = n_1 \paren {h_1 n_2 h_1^{-1} h_1} h_2 }} {{eqn | r = n_1 \paren {h_1 n_2 h_1^{-1} } \paren {h_1 h_2} }} {{end-eqn}} Since $N$ is normal in $G$: :$\exists n \in N: n = h_1 n_2 h_1^{-1}$ Thus: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = \paren {n_1 h_1} \paren {n_2 h_2} | r = \paren {n_1 n} \paren {h_1 h_2} }} {{eqn | o = \in | r = N H }} {{end-eqn}} Also: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = \paren {n_1 h_1}^{-1} | r = h_1^{-1} n_1^{-1} }} {{eqn | r = \paren {h_1^{-1} n_1^{-1} h_1} h_1^{-1} }} {{eqn | o = \in | r = N H }} {{end-eqn}} so from the Two-Step Subgroup Test, $N H$ is a subgroup of $G$. The fact that $N H = H N$ follows from Subset Product of Subgroups. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21969
\section{Subset Product within Commutative Structure is Commutative} Tags: Subset Products, Abstract Algebra \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {S, \circ}$ be a magma. If $\circ$ is commutative, then the operation $\circ_\PP$ induced on the power set of $S$ is also commutative. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Let $\struct {S, \circ}$ be a magma in which $\circ$ is commutative. Let $X, Y \in \powerset S$. Then: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = X \circ_\PP Y | r = \set {x \circ y: x \in X, y \in Y} }} {{eqn | l = Y \circ_\PP X | r = \set {y \circ x: x \in X, y \in Y} }} {{end-eqn}} from which it follows that $\circ_\PP$ is commutative on $\powerset S$. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21970
\section{Subset Product within Semigroup is Associative} Tags: Semigroups, Abstract Algebra, Subset Products, Subset Product within Semigroup is Associative, Associativity \begin{theorem} Let $\struct {S, \circ}$ be a semigroup. Then the operation $\circ_\PP$ induced on the power set of $S$ is also associative. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Let $X, Y, Z \in \powerset S$. Then: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = X \circ_\PP \paren {Y \circ_\PP Z} | r = \set {x \circ \paren {y \circ z}: x \in X, y \in Y, z \in Z} | c = }} {{eqn | r = \set {\paren {x \circ y} \circ z: x \in X, y \in Y, z \in Z} | c = }} {{eqn | r = \paren {X \circ_\PP Y} \circ_\PP Z | c = }} {{end-eqn}} demonstrating that $\circ_\PP$ is associative on $\powerset S$. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21971
\section{Subset Product within Semigroup is Associative/Corollary} Tags: Subset Products, Subset Product within Semigroup is Associative \begin{theorem} Let $\left({S, \circ}\right)$ be a magma. If $\circ$ is associative, then: * $x \left({y S}\right) = \left({x y}\right) S$ * $x \left({S y}\right) = \left({x S}\right) y$ * $\left({S x}\right) y = S \left({x y}\right)$ \end{theorem} \begin{proof} From the definition of Subset Product with Singleton: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = x \paren {y S} | r = \set x \paren {\set y S} }} {{eqn | l = x \paren {S y} | r = \set x \paren {S \set y} }} {{eqn | l = \paren {S x} y | r = \paren {S \set x} \set y }} {{end-eqn}} The result then follows directly from Subset Product within Semigroup is Associative. {{qed}} \end{proof}
21972
\section{Subset Products of Normal Subgroup with Normal Subgroup of Subgroup} Tags: Normal Subgroups, Subset Products \begin{theorem} Let $G$ be a group. Let: :$(1): \quad H$ be a subgroup of $G$ :$(2): \quad K$ be a normal subgroup of $H$ :$(3): \quad N$ be a normal subgroup of $G$ Then: :$N K \lhd N H$ where: : $N K$ and $N H$ denote subset product : $\lhd$ denotes the relation of being a normal subgroup. \end{theorem} \begin{proof} Consider arbitrary $x_n \in N, x_h \in H$. Thus: :$x_n x_h \in N H$ We aim to show that: :$x_n x_h N K \paren {x_n x_h}^{-1} \subseteq N K$ thus demonstrating $N K \lhd N H$ by the Normal Subgroup Test. We have: {{begin-eqn}} {{eqn | l = x_n x_h N K \paren {x_n x_h}^{-1} | r = x_n x_h N K {x_h}^{-1} {x_n}^{-1} | c = Inverse of Group Product }} {{eqn | r = x_n N x_h K {x_h}^{-1} {x_n}^{-1} | c = as $N \lhd G$ and $H \le G$ }} {{eqn | r = x_n N K {x_n}^{-1} | c = as $K \lhd H$ }} {{eqn | r = N K {x_n}^{-1} }} {{eqn | r = K N {x_n}^{-1} | c = as $N \lhd G$ and $K \le G$ }} {{eqn | r = K N }} {{eqn | r = N K | c = as $N \lhd G$ and $K \le G$ }} {{end-eqn}} {{qed}} \end{proof}