Unnamed: 0
int64
0
41k
title
stringlengths
4
274
category
stringlengths
5
18
summary
stringlengths
22
3.66k
theme
stringclasses
8 values
1,800
A note on canonical functions
math.LO
We construct a generic extension in which the aleph_2 nd canonical function on aleph_1 exists.
math
1,801
Categoricity over P for first order T or categoricity for phi in L_{omega_1 omega} can stop at aleph_k while holding for aleph_0, ..., aleph_{k-1}
math.LO
Suppose L is a relational language and P in L is a unary predicate. If M is an L-structure then P(M) is the L-structure formed as the substructure of M with domain {a: M models P(a)}. Now suppose T is a complete first order theory in L with infinite models. Following Hodges, we say that T is relatively lambda-categorical if whenever M, N models T, P(M)=P(N), |P(M)|= lambda then there is an isomorphism i:M-> N which is the identity on P(M). T is relatively categorical if it is relatively lambda-categorical for every lambda. The question arises whether the relative lambda-categoricity of T for some lambda >|T| implies that T is relatively categorical. In this paper, we provide an example, for every k>0, of a theory T_k and an L_{omega_1 omega} sentence varphi_k so that T_k is relatively aleph_n-categorical for n < k and varphi_k is aleph_n-categorical for n<k but T_k is not relatively beth_k-categorical and varphi_k is not beth_k-categorical.
math
1,802
The primal framework. I
math.LO
This the first of a series of articles dealing with abstract classification theory. The apparatus to assign systems of cardinal invariants to models of a first order theory (or determine its impossibility) is developed in [Sh:a]. It is natural to try to extend this theory to classes of models which are described in other ways. Work on the classification theory for nonelementary classes [Sh:88] and for universal classes [Sh:300] led to the conclusion that an axiomatic approach provided the best setting for developing a theory of wider application. In the first chapter we describe the axioms on which the remainder of the article depends and give some examples and context to justify this level of generality. The study of universal classes takes as a primitive the notion of closing a subset under functions to obtain a model. We replace that concept by the notion of a prime model. We begin the detailed discussion of this idea in Chapter II. One of the important contributions of classification theory is the recognition that large models can often be analyzed by means of a family of small models indexed by a tree of height at most omega. More precisely, the analyzed model is prime over such a tree. Chapter III provides sufficient conditions for prime models over such trees to exist.
math
1,803
Full reflection of stationary sets below aleph_omega
math.LO
It is consistent that for every n >= 2, every stationary subset of omega_n consisting of ordinals of cofinality omega_k where k = 0 or k <= n-3 reflects fully in the set of ordinals of cofinality omega_{n-1}. We also show that this result is best possible.
math
1,804
The Hanf numbers of stationary logic. II. Comparison with other logics
math.LO
We show that the ordering of the Hanf number of L_{omega, omega}(wo) (well ordering), L^c_{omega, omega} (quantification on countable sets), L_{omega, omega}(aa) (stationary logic) and second order logic, have no more restraints provable in ZFC than previously known (those independence proofs assume CON(ZFC) only). We also get results on corresponding logics for L_{lambda, mu} .
math
1,805
Strong partition relations below the power set: consistency, was Sierpinski right, II?
math.LO
We continue here [Sh276] but we do not relay on it. The motivation was a conjecture of Galvin stating that 2^{omega} >= omega_2 + omega_2-> [omega_1]^{n}_{h(n)} is consistent for a suitable h: omega-> omega. In section 5 we disprove this and give similar negative results. In section 3 we prove the consistency of the conjecture replacing omega_2 by 2^omega, which is quite large, starting with an Erd\H{o}s cardinal. In section 1 we present iteration lemmas which are needed when we replace omega by a larger lambda and in section 4 we generalize a theorem of Halpern and Lauchli replacing omega by a larger lambda .
math
1,806
Viva la difference I: Nonisomorphism of ultrapowers of countable models
math.LO
We show that it is not provable in ZFC that any two countable elementarily equivalent structures have isomorphic ultrapowers relative to some ultrafilter on omega .
math
1,807
The primal framework. II. Smoothness
math.LO
This is the second in a series of articles developing abstract classification theory for classes that have a notion of prime models over independent pairs and over chains. It deals with the problem of smoothness and establishing the existence and uniqueness of a `monster model'. We work here with a predicate for a canonically prime model.
math
1,808
On a conjecture of Tarski on products of cardinals
math.LO
We look at an old conjecture of A. Tarski on cardinal arithmetic and show that if a counterexample exists, then there exists one of length omega_1 + omega .
math
1,809
A partition theorem for pairs of finite sets
math.LO
Every partition of [[omega_1]^{< omega}]^2 into finitely many pieces has a cofinal homogeneous set. Furthermore, it is consistent that every directed partially ordered set satisfies the partition property if and only if it has finite character.
math
1,810
Coding and reshaping when there are no sharps
math.LO
Assuming 0^sharp does not exist, kappa is an uncountable cardinal and for all cardinals lambda with kappa <= lambda < kappa^{+ omega}, 2^lambda = lambda^+, we present a ``mini-coding'' between kappa and kappa^{+ omega}. This allows us to prove that any subset of kappa^{+ omega} can be coded into a subset, W of kappa^+ which, further, ``reshapes'' the interval [kappa, kappa^+), i.e., for all kappa < delta < kappa^+, kappa = (card delta)^{L[W cap delta]}. We sketch two applications of this result, assuming 0^sharp does not exist. First, we point out that this shows that any set can be coded by a real, via a set forcing. The second application involves a notion of abstract condensation, due to Woodin. Our methods can be used to show that for any cardinal mu, condensation for mu holds in a generic extension by a set forcing.
math
1,811
Cardinal arithmetic for skeptics
math.LO
We present a survey of some results of the pcf-theory and their applications to cardinal arithmetic. We review basics notions (in section 1), briefly look at history in section 2 (and some personal history in section 3). We present main results on pcf in section 5 and describe applications to cardinal arithmetic in section 6. The limitations on independence proofs are discussed in section 7, and in section 8 we discuss the status of two axioms that arise in the new setting. Applications to other areas are found in section 9.
math
1,812
The universality spectrum of stable unsuperstable theories
math.LO
It is shown that if T is stable unsuperstable, and aleph_1< lambda =cf(lambda)< 2^{aleph_0}, or 2^{aleph_0} < mu^+< lambda =cf(lambda)< mu^{aleph_0} then T has no universal model in cardinality lambda, and if e.g. aleph_omega < 2^{aleph_0} then T has no universal model in aleph_omega. These results are generalized to kappa =cf(kappa) < kappa (T) in the place of aleph_0. Also: if there is a universal model in lambda >|T|, T stable and kappa < kappa (T) then there is a universal tree of height kappa +1 in cardinality lambda .
math
1,813
Constructing strongly equivalent nonisomorphic models for unsuperstable theories. Part B
math.LO
We study how equivalent nonisomorphic models of unsuperstable theories can be. We measure the equivalence by Ehrenfeucht-Fraisse games. This paper continues [HySh:474].
math
1,814
On the Singular Cardinal Hypothesis
math.LO
We use the core model for sequences of measures to prove a new lower bound for the consistency strength of the failure of the SCH: THEOREM (i) If there is a singular strong limit cardinal $\kappa$ such that $2^\kappa > kappa^+$ then there is an inner model with a cardinal $\kappa$ such that for all ordinals $\alpha<\kappa$ there is an ordinal $\nu < \kappa$ with $o(\nu) > \alpha$. (ii) If there is a singular strong limit cardinal $\kappa$ of uncountable cofinality such that $2^\kappa > \kappa^+$ then there is an inner model with $o(\kappa) = \kappa^{++}$. Since this paper was originally submitted, Gitik has improved this result to give exact lower bounds.
math
1,815
A division Algorithm for the Free Left Distributive Algebra
math.LO
The normal form theorem, proved in R. Laver, On the left distributive law and the freeness of an algebra of elementary embeddings, Advances in Mathematics 91 (1992), 209-231, for the free algebra $\Cal A$ on one generator $x$ satisfying the left distributive law $a(bc) = (ab)(ac)$ is extended by showing that members of $\Cal A$ can be put into a "division form."
math
1,816
On the Algebra of Elementary Embeddings of a Rank into Inself
math.LO
Let $j:V_\lambda---> V_\lambda$ be an elementary embedding, with critical point $\kappa$, and let $f(n)$ be the number of critical points of embeddings in the algebra generated by $j$ which lie between $j^n(\kappa)$ and $j^{n+1}(\kappa)$. It is shown that $f(n)$ is finite for all $n$.
math
1,817
Maximal Chains in {}^ωωand Ultrapowers of the Integers
math.LO
Various questions posed by P. Nyikos concerning ultrafilters on $\omega$ and chains in the partial order $(\omega,<^*)$ are answered. The main tool is the oracle chain condition and variations of it.
math
1,818
A short proof of the irreflexivity conjecture
math.LO
Gives a short proof of Dehornoy's latest result. The same simple argument (and more) was discovered by Laver's student Larue.
math
1,819
On Gödel's second incompleteness theorem
math.LO
A very short proof of G\"odel's second incompleteness theorem (for set theory, second order arithmetic etc.)
math
1,820
On Braid Words and Irreflexivity
math.LO
The purpose of this note is to prove irreflexivity, and hence the linear ordering, in ZFC, without some of the machinery used by Dehornoy.
math
1,821
Embeddings of Iteration Trees
math.LO
This paper, dating from May 1991, contains preliminary (and unpublishable) notes on investigations about iteration trees. They will be of interest only to the specialist. In the first two sections I define notions of support and embeddings for tree iterations, proving for example that every tree iteration is a direct limit of finite tree iterations. This is a generalization to models with extenders of basic ideas of iterated ultrapowers using only ultrapowers. In the final section (which is most of the paper) I sketch a proof that any tree iteration can be embedded into a normal iteration, that is, a tree iteration with the extenders in nondecreasing order of strength and with strictly increasing critical points.
math
1,822
Reaping Numbers of Boolean Algebras
math.LO
A subset $A$ of a Boolean algebra $B$ is said to be $(n,m)$-reaped if there is a partition of unity $P \subset B$ of size $n$ such that the cardinality of $\{b \in P: b \wedge a \neq \emptyset\}$ is greater than or equal to $m$ for all $a\in A$. The reaping number $r_{n,m}(B)$ of a Boolean algebra $B$ is the minimum cardinality of a set $A \subset B\setminus \{0\}$ such which cannot be $(n,m)$-reaped. It is shown that, for each $n \in \omega$, there is a Boolean algebra $B$ such that $r_{n+1,2}(B) \neq r_{n,2}(B)$. Also, $\{r_{n,m}(B) : \{n,m\}\subseteq\omega\}$ consists of at most two consecutive integers. The existence of a Boolean algebra $B$ such that $r_{n,m}(B) \neq r_{n',m'}(B)$ is equivalent to a statement in finite combinatorics which is also discussed.
math
1,823
Full reflection of stationary sets at regular cardinals
math.LO
A stationary subset S of a regular uncountable cardinal kappa reflects fully at regular cardinals if for every stationary set T subseteq kappa of higher order consisting of regular cardinals there exists an alpha in T such that S cap alpha is a stationary subset of alpha. We prove that the Axiom of Full Reflection which states that every stationary set reflects fully at regular cardinals, together with the existence of n-Mahlo cardinals is equiconsistent with the existence of Pi^1_n-indescribable cardinals. We also state the appropriate generalization for greatly Mahlo cardinals.
math
1,824
The Cardinality of the second uniform indiscernible
math.LO
When the second uniform indiscernible is $\aleph_{2}$, the Martin-Solovay tree only constructs countably many reals; this resolves a number of open questions in descriptive set theory.
math
1,825
Critical points in an algebra of elementary embeddings
math.LO
Given two elementary embeddings from the collection of sets of rank less than $\lambda$ to itself, one can combine them to obtain another such embedding in two ways: by composition, and by applying one to (initial segments of) the other. Hence, a single such nontrivial embedding $j$ generates an algebra of embeddings via these two operations, which satisfies certain laws (for example, application distributes over both composition and application). Laver has shown, among other things, that this algebra is free on one generator with respect to these laws. The set of critical points of members of this algebra is the subject of this paper. This set contains the critical point $\kappa_0$ of $j$, as well as all of the other ordinals $\kappa_n$ in the critical sequence of $j$ (defined by $\kappa_{n+1} = j(\kappa_n)$). But the set includes many other ordinals as well. The main result of this paper is that the number of critical points below $\kappa_n$ (which has been shown to be finite by Laver and Steel) grows so quickly with $n$ that it dominates any primitive recursive function. In fact, it grows faster than the Ackermann function, and even faster than a slow iterate of the Ackermann function. Further results show that, even just below $\kappa_4$, one can find so many critical points that the number is only expressible using fast-growing hierarchies of iterated functions (six levels of iteration beyond exponentials).
math
1,826
Many simple cardinal invariants
math.LO
For g < f in omega^omega we define c(f,g) be the least number of uniform trees with g-splitting needed to cover a uniform tree with f-splitting. We show that we can simultaneously force aleph_1 many different values for different functions (f,g). In the language of Blass: There may be aleph_1 many distinct uniform Pi^0_1 characteristics.
math
1,827
Covering games and the Banach-Mazur game: k-tactics
math.LO
Given a free ideal J of subsets of a set X, we consider games where player ONE plays an increasing sequence of elements of the sigma completion of J, and TWO tries to cover the union of this sequence by playing one set at a time from J. We describe various conditions under which player TWO has has a winning strategy that uses only information about the most recent k moves of ONE, and apply some of these results to the Banach-Mazur game.
math
1,828
Donder's Version of Revised Countable Support
math.LO
Shelah introduced the revised countable support (RCS) iteration to iterate semiproperness. This was an endpoint in the search for an iteration of a weak condition, still implying that aleph1 is preserved. Dieter Donder found a better manageable approach to this iteration, which is presented here.
math
1,829
Remark on the Failure of Martin's Axiom
math.LO
Let m be the least cardinal k such that MA(k) fails. The only known model for "m is singular" was constructed by Kunen. In Kunen's model cof(m)=omega_1. It is unknown whether "omega_1 < cof(m) < m" is consistent. The purpose of this paper is to present a proof of Kunen's result and to identify the difficulties of generalizing this result to an arbitrary uncountable cofinality.
math
1,830
Non-existence of Universal Orders in Many Cardinals
math.LO
Our theme is that not every interesting question in set theory is independent of $ZFC$. We give an example of a first order theory $T$ with countable $D(T)$ which cannot have a universal model at $\aleph_1$ without CH; we prove in $ZFC$ a covering theorem from the hypothesis of the existence of a universal model for some theory; and we prove --- again in ZFC --- that for a large class of cardinals there is no universal linear order (e.g. in every $\aleph_1<\l<2^{\aleph_0}$). In fact, what we show is that if there is a universal linear order at a regular $\l$ and its existence is not a result of a trivial cardinal arithmetical reason, then $\l$ ``resembles'' $\aleph_1$ --- a cardinal for which the consistency of having a universal order is known. As for singular cardinals, we show that for many singular cardinals, if they are not strong limits then they have no universal linear order. As a result of the non existence of a universal linear order, we show the non-existence of universal models for all theories possessing the strict order property (for example, ordered fields and groups, Boolean algebras, p-adic rings and fields, partial orders, models of PA and so on).
math
1,831
Finite left-distributive algebras and embedding algebras\endtitle
math.LO
We consider algebras with one binary operation $\cdot$ and one generator ({\it monogenic}) and satisfying the left distributive law $a\cdot (b\cdot c)=(a\cdot b)\cdot (a\cdot c)$. One can define a sequence of finite left-distributive algebras $A_n$, and then take a limit to get an infinite monogenic left-distributive algebra~$A_\infty$. Results of Laver and Steel assuming a strong large cardinal axiom imply that $A_\infty$ is free; it is open whether the freeness of $A_\infty$ can be proved without the large cardinal assumption, or even in Peano arithmetic. The main result of this paper is the equivalence of this problem with the existence of a certain algebra of increasing functions on natural numbers, called an {\it embedding algebra}. Using this and results of the first author, we conclude that the freeness of $A_\infty$ is unprovable in primitive recursive arithmetic.
math
1,832
Cardinal Characteristics and the Product of Countably Many Infinite Cyclic Groups
math.LO
Let P be the direct product of countably many copies of the additive group Z of integers. We study, from a set-theoretic point of view, those subgroups of P for which all homomorphisms to Z annihilate all but finitely many of the standard unit vectors. Specifically, we relate the smallest possible size of such a subgroup to several of the standard cardinal characteristics of the continuum. We also study some related properties and cardinals, both group-theoretic and set-theoretic. One of the set-theoretic properties and the associated cardinal are combinatorially natural, independently of any connection with algebra.
math
1,833
$μ$-complete Souslin trees on $μ^+$
math.LO
We prove that $\mu=\mu^{<\mu}$, $2^\mu=\mu^+$ and ``there is a non reflecting stationary subset of $\mu^+$ composed of ordinals of cofinality $<\mu$'' imply that there is a $\mu$-complete Souslin tree on $\mu^+$.
math
1,834
Perfect sets of random reals
math.LO
We discuss the relationship between perfect sets of random reals, dominating reals, and the product of two copies of the random algebra B. Recall that B is the algebra of Borel sets of 2^omega modulo the null sets. Also given two models M subseteq N of ZFC, we say that g in omega^omega cap N is a dominating real over M iff forall f in omega^omega cap M there is m in omega such that forall n geq m (g(n) > f(n)); and r in 2^omega cap N is random over M iff r avoids all Borel null sets coded in M iff r is determined by some filter which is B-generic over M. We show that there is a ccc partial order P which adds a perfect set of random reals without adding a dominating real, thus answering a question asked by the second author in joint work with T. Bartoszynski and S. Shelah some time ago. The method of the proof of this result yields also that B times B does not add a dominating real. By a different argument we show that B times B does not add a perfect set of random reals (this answers a question that A. Miller asked during the logic year at MSRI).
math
1,835
Amoeba-absoluteness and projective measurability
math.LO
We study the relationship between Amoeba forcing (the partial order which generically adds a measure one set of random reals) and projective measurability. Given a universe V of set theory and a forcing notion P in V we say that V is Sigma^1_n - P - absolute iff for every Sigma^1_n-sentence phi with parameters in V we have V models phi iff V^P models phi. We show that Sigma^1_4-Amoeba-absoluteness implies that forall a in omega^omega (omega_1^{L[a]} < omega_1^V), and hence Sigma^1_3-measurability. This answers a question of Haim Judah (private communication).
math
1,836
Finite Combinations of Baire Numbers
math.LO
Let $\kappa$ be a regular cardinal. Consider the Baire numbers of the spaces $(2^{\theta})_\kappa$ (functions from $\theta$ to 2 and the less than $\kappa$ topology) for various $\theta \geq \kappa$. Let l be the number of such different Baire numbers. Models of set theory with l=1 or l=2 are known and it is also known that l is finite. We show here that if $\kappa > \omega$, then l could be any given finite number. We do not know whether the same is true for $\kappa = \omega$.
math
1,837
Meager-nowhere dense games (III): Remainder strategies
math.LO
Player ONE chooses a meager set and player TWO, a nowhere dense set per inning. They play $\omega$ many innings. ONE's consecutive choices must form a (weakly) increasing sequence. TWO wins if the union of the chosen nowhere dense sets covers the union of the chosen meager sets. A strategy for TWO which depends on knowing only the uncovered part of the most recently chosen meager set is said to be a remainder strategy. Theorem (among others): TWO has a winning remainder strategy for this game played on the real line with its usual topology.
math
1,838
Some Natural Internal Forcing Schemata Extending ZFC
math.LO
We give arguments for and prove the consistency of some internal forcing axioms.
math
1,839
$^*$Forcing
math.LO
Let $M$ be a transitive model of $ZFC$ and let ${\bf B}$ be a $M$-complete Boolean algebra in $M.$ (In general a proper class.) We define a generalized notion of forcing with such Boolean algebras, $^*$forcing. (A $^*$ forcing extension of $M$ is a transitive set of the form $M[{\bf G}]$ where ${\bf G}$ is an $M$-complete ultrafilter on ${\bf B}.$) We prove that 1. If ${\bf G}$ is a $^*$forcing complete ultrafilter on ${\bf B},$ then $M[{\bf G}]\models ZFC.$ 2. Let $H\sub M.$ If there is a least transitive model $N$ such that $H\in M,$ $Ord^M=Ord^N,$ and $N\models ZFC,$ then we denote $N$ by $M[H].$ We show that all models of $ZFC$ of the form $M[H]$ are $^*$forcing extensions of $M.$ As an immediate corollary we get that $L[0^{\#}]$ is a $^*$forcing extension of $L.$
math
1,840
The Complexity of the Core Model
math.LO
We use the Sigma^1_3 absoluteness theorem to show that the complexity of the statement "(omega,E)$ is isomorphic to an initial segment of the core model" is Pi^1_4, and that the complexity of the statement "(omega,E)$ is isomorphic to a member of the core model" is Delta^1_5.
math
1,841
Reflection and Weakly Collectionwise Hausdorff Spaces
math.LO
We show that square(theta) implies that there is a first countable <theta-collectionwise Hausdorff space that is not weakly theta-collectionwise Hausdorff. We also show that in the model obtained by Levy collapsing a weakly compact (supercompact) cardinal to omega_2, first countable aleph_1-collectionwise Hausdorff spaces are weakly aleph_2-collectionwise Hausdorff (weakly collectionwise Hausdorff). In the last section we show that assuming E^omega_theta, a certain theta-family of integer valued functions exists and that in the model obtained by Levy collapsing a supercompact cardinal to omega_2, these families do not exist.
math
1,842
Splitting number and the core model
math.LO
We can generalize the definition of {\it splitting number } $s(\kappa )$ for $\kappa$ uncountable regular: $s(\kappa )=min\{ |\Cal S|:\Cal S\subset \Cal P(\kappa ) \forall a\in \kappa ^\kappa \exists b\in \Cal S |a\cap b|=|a\setminus b|=\kappa\}$ However,$\exists \kappa>\aleph_0$ $s(\kappa )>\kappa ^+$ becomes a considerable hypothesis,shown consistent from a supercompact.We show that it implies inner models of $\exists \alpha :o(\alpha )=\alpha ^{++}$
math
1,843
Set-theoretic aspects of periodic $FC$-groups --- extraspecial p-groups and Kurepa trees
math.LO
Given a group G, we let Z(G) denote its center, G' its commutator subgroup, and Phi (G) its Frattini subgroup (the intersection of all maximal proper subgroups of G). Given U leq G, we let N_G (U) stand for the normalizer of U in G. A group G is FC iff every element g in G has finitely many conjugates. A p-group E is called extraspecial iff Phi (E) = E' = Z(E) cong Z_p, the cyclic group with p elements. When generalizing a characterization of centre-by-finite groups due to B. H. Neumann, M. J. Tomkinson asked the following question. Is there an FC-group G with vert G / Z(G) vert = kappa but [G:N_G(U)] < kappa for all (abelian) subgroups U of G, where kappa is an uncountable cardinal. We consider this question for kappa = omega_1 and kappa = omega_2. It turns out that the answer is largely independent of ZFC, and that it differs greatly in the two cases. More explicitly, for kappa = omega_1, it is consistent with, and independent of, ZFC that there is a group G with vert G / Z(G) vert = omega_1 and [G:N_G (A)] leq omega for all abelian A leq G. We do not know whether the same statement is still consistent if we drop abelian. On the other hand, for kappa = omega_2, the non-existence of groups G with vert G / Z(G) vert = omega_2 and [G : N_G (A) ] leq omega_1 for all (abelian) A leq G is equiconsistent with the existence of an inaccessible cardinal. In particular, there is an extraspecial p-group with this property if there is a Kurepa tree.
math
1,844
Combinatorial properties of Hechler forcing
math.LO
In this work we use a notion of rank first introduced by James Baumgartner and Peter Dordal and later developed independently by the third author to show that adding a Hechler real has strong combinatorial consequences. We prove: 1) assuming omega_1^V = omega_1^L, there is no real in V[d] which is eventually different from the reals in L[d], where d is Hechler over V; 2) adding one Hechler real makes the invariants on the left-hand side of Cicho'n's diagram equal omega_1 and those on the right-hand side equal 2^omega and produces a maximal almost disjoint family of subsets of omega of size omega_1; 3) there is no perfect set of random reals over V in V[r][d], where r is random over V and d Hechler over V[r], thus answering a question of the first and second authors. As an intermediate step in the proof of 3) we show that given models M subseteq N of ZFC such that there is a perfect set of random reals in N over M, either there is a dominating real in N over M or mu (2^omega cap M) = 0 in N.
math
1,845
The Genericity Conjecture
math.LO
In this paper we produce a real r such that 0<r<0# in L-degree, yet R is NOT generic over L (for a forcing amenable to L). This answers a question of Beller-Jensen-Welch.
math
1,846
A simpler proof of Jensen's coding theorem
math.LO
We present a simplification of Jensen's proof of his Coding Theorem (even in the case where 0# exists). The proof avoids Jensen's split into cases according to whether or not 0# exists. In addition, the paper contains self-contained proofs of the necessary forms of Square and Diamond, based on an approach to fine structure using Jensen's $\Sigma^*$ theory.
math
1,847
Minimal universes
math.LO
An inner model M is MINIMAL if there is a class A such that <M,A> is amenable yet has no transitive proper elementary submodel. We study minimal universes in the context of 0#. For example we prove: If 0# exists then there is an inner model which is minimal and locally generic over L(i.e., every set in the inner model is set-generic over L). This answers a question of Mack Stanley.
math
1,848
Measurable rectangles
math.LO
We give an example of a measurable set of reals E such that the set E'={(x,y): x+y in E} is not in the sigma-algebra generated by the rectangles with measurable sides. We also prove a stronger result that there exists an analytic set E such that E' is not in the sigma-algebra generated by rectangles whose horizontal side is measurable and vertical side is arbitrary. The same results are true when measurable is replaced with property of Baire.
math
1,849
Baire property and Axiom of Choice
math.LO
We show that (1) If ZF is consistent then the following theory is consistent "ZF + DC(omega_{1}) + Every set of reals has Baire property" and (2) If ZF is consistent then the following theory is consistent "ZFC + `every projective set of reals has Baire property' + `any union of omega_{1} meager sets is meager' ".
math
1,850
Planting Kurepa trees and killing Jech-Kunen trees in a model by using one inaccessible cardinal
math.LO
By an omega_1--tree we mean a tree of power omega_1 and height omega_1. Under CH and 2^{omega_1}> omega_2 we call an omega_1--tree a Jech--Kunen tree if it has kappa many branches for some kappa strictly between omega_1 and 2^{omega_1}. In this paper we prove that, assuming the existence of one inaccessible cardinal, (1) it is consistent with CH plus 2^{omega_1}> omega_2 that there exist Kurepa trees and there are no Jech--Kunen trees, (2) it is consistent with CH plus 2^{omega_1}= omega_4 that only Kurepa trees with omega_3 many branches exist.
math
1,851
Jensen's Σ^* theory and the combinatorial content of V=L
math.LO
The purpose of this article is to indicate how a reformulation of Jensen's $\Sigma^*$ theory (developed for the study of core models) can be used to provide a more satisfactory treatment of uniformization, hulls and Skolem functions for the $J_\alpha$'s. Then we use this approach to fine structure to formulate a principle intended to capture the combinatorial content of the axiom $V=L.$
math
1,852
A large Pi-1-2 set absolute for set forcing
math.LO
Let k be a definable L-cardinal. Then there is a set of reals X, class-generic over L, such that L(X) and L have the same cardinals, X has size k in L(X) and some pi-1-2 formula defines X in all set-generic extensions of L(X). Two corollaries, both assuming the consistency of an inaccessible: It is consistent for the Perfect Set Property to hold for boldface sigma-1-2 sets, yet fail for some lightface pi-1-2 set. It is consistent that the Perfect Set Property holds for boldface sigma-1-2 sets yet some lightface pi-1-2 wellordering of some set of reals has length aleph-1000.
math
1,853
Some compact logics --- results in ZFC
math.LO
We show that if we enrich first order logic by allowing quantification over isomorphisms between definable ordered fields the resulting logic, L(Q_{Of}), is fully compact. In this logic, we can give standard compactness proofs of various results. Next, we attempt to get compactness results for some other logics without recourse to diamond, i.e., all our results are in ZFC. We get the full result for the language where we quantify over automorphisms (isomorphisms) of ordered fields in Theorem 6.4. Unfortunately we are not able to show that the language with quantification over automorphisms of Boolean algebras is compact, but will have to settle for a close relative of that logic. This is theorem 5.1. In section 4 we prove we can construct models in which all relevant automorphism are somewhat definable: 4.1, 4.8 for BA, 4.13 for ordered fields. We also give a new proof of the compactness of another logic -- the one which is obtained when a quantifier Q_{Brch} is added to first order logic which says that a level tree (definitions will be given later) has an infinite branch. This logic was previously shown to be compact, but our proof yields a somewhat stronger result and provides a nice illustration of one of our methods.
math
1,854
On the number of automorphism of uncontable models
math.LO
Let s(A) denote the number of automorphisms of a model A of power omega_1. We derive a necessary and sufficient condition in terms of trees for the existence of an A with omega_1 < s(A) < 2^{omega_1}. We study the sufficiency of some conditions for s(A)=2^{omega_1}. These conditions are analogous to conditions studied by D.Kueker in connection with countable models.
math
1,855
All meager filters may be null
math.LO
We show that it is consistent with ZFC that all filters which have the Baire property are Lebesgue measurable. We also show that the existence of a Sierpinski set implies that there exists a nonmeasurable filter which has the Baire property.
math
1,856
Forcing isomorphism
math.LO
A forcing extension may create new isomorphisms between two models of a first order theory. Certain model theoretic constraints on the theory and other constraints on the forcing can prevent this pathology. A countable first order theory is classifiable if it is superstable and does not have either the dimensional order property or the omitting types order property. Shelah [Sh:c] showed that if a theory T is classifiable then each model of cardinality lambda is described by a sentence of L_{infty, lambda}. In fact this sentence can be chosen in the L^*_{lambda}. (L^*_{lambda} is the result of enriching the language L_{infty, beth^+} by adding for each mu < lambda a quantifier saying the dimension of a dependence structure is greater than mu .) The truth of such sentences will be preserved by any forcing that does not collapse cardinals <= lambda and that adds no new countable subsets of lambda. Hence, if two models of a classifiable theory of power lambda are non-isomorphic, they are non-isomorphic after a lambda-complete forcing. Here we show that the hypothesis of the forcing adding no new countable subsets of lambda cannot be eliminated. In particular, we show that non-isomorphism of models of a classifiable theory need not be preserved by ccc forcings.
math
1,857
Borel partitions of infinite subtrees of a perfect tree
math.LO
A theorem of Galvin asserts that if the unordered pairs of reals are partitioned into finitely many Borel classes then there is a perfect set P such that all pairs from P lie in the same class. The generalization to n-tuples for n >= 3 is false. Let us identify the reals with 2^omega ordered by the lexicographical ordering and define for distinct x,y in 2^omega, D(x,y) to be the least n such that x(n) not= y(n). Let the type of an increasing n-tuple {x_0, ... x_{n-1}}_< be the ordering <^* on {0, ...,n-2} defined by i<^*j iff D(x_i,x_{i+1})< D(x_j,x_{j+1}). Galvin proved that for any Borel coloring of triples of reals there is a perfect set P such that the color of any triple from P depends only on its type. Blass proved an analogous result is true for any n. As a corollary it follows that if the unordered n-tuples of reals are colored into finitely many Borel classes there is a perfect set P such that the n-tuples from P meet at most (n-1)! classes. We consider extensions of this result to partitions of infinite increasing sequences of reals. We show, that for any Borel or even analytic partition of all increasing sequences of reals there is a perfect set P such that all strongly increasing sequences from P lie in the same class.
math
1,858
On the existence of atomic models
math.LO
We give an example of a countable theory T such that for every cardinal lambda >= aleph_2 there is a fully indiscernible set A of power lambda such that the principal types are dense over A, yet there is no atomic model of T over A. In particular, T(A) is a theory of size lambda where the principal types are dense, yet T(A) has no atomic model.
math
1,859
Provable Pi-1-2 Singletons
math.LO
In this note I show that a pi-1-2 singleton R of L-degree strictly between 0 and 0# can be obtained so as to be the unique solution to a pi-1-2 formula which provably has at most one solution, in the theory ZFC+(*) where (*) has the approximate strength of an ineffable cardinal.
math
1,860
Full Reflection at a Measurable Cardinal
math.LO
A stationary subset $S$ of a regular uncountable cardinal $\kappa$ {\it reflects fully} at regular cardinals if for every stationary set $T \subseteq \kappa$ of higher order consisting of regular cardinals there exists an $\alpha \in T$ such that $S \cap \alpha$ is a stationary subset of $\alpha$. {\it Full Reflection} states that every stationary set reflects fully at regular cardinals. We will prove that under a slightly weaker assumption than $\kappa$ having Mitchell order $\kappa^{++}$ it is consistent that Full Reflection holds at every $\lambda \leq \kappa$ and $\kappa$ is measurable.
math
1,861
Combinatorics on Ideals and Axiom A
math.LO
Throughout this abstract let U be a fixed p-point ultrafilter and let I be the dual ideal. Grigorieff forcing is P(U)={p:omega to 2|dom(p) is an element of I} ordered by reverse inclusion. It is well known that Grigorieff forcing is proper. The main result of this paper is the following: THEOREM: Gregorieff forcing does not satisfy Axiom A. To prove this we use the following game, denoted G(U), for two players playing alternatively: Player I plays a partition of omega, {J_n| n<omega}, such that for all n<omega, J_n is an element of I; At the nth turn Player II plays a finite subset F_n of J_n. Player II wins iff the union of the F_n is an element of U. The following two Lemmas prove the Theorem: LEMMA 1: If P(U) satisfies axiom A, then player II has a winning strategy in the game G(U). LEMMA 2:The game G(U) is undetermined.
math
1,862
The automorphism group of a saturated model has a large dense free subgroup
math.LO
We prove that for a stable theory $T,$ if $M$ is a saturated model of $T$ of cardinality $\lambda$ where $\lambda > \big|T\big|,$ then $Aut(M)$ has a dense free subgroup on $2^{\lambda}$ generators. This affirms a conjecture of Hodges.
math
1,863
Natural Internal Forcing Schemata Extending ZFC
math.LO
Let V be the universe of sets and V_{\alpha} the sets of rank \leq\alpha. We develop some axiom schemata for set theory based on the following three assumptions: 1. V \models ZFC 2. V is large with respect to the class of ordinals 3. V is large with respect to each of the V_{\alpha}
math
1,864
The Consistency of $ZFC+CIFS$
math.LO
This paper is a technical continuation of ``Natural Axiom Schemata Extending ZFC. Truth in the Universe?'' In that paper we argue that $CIFS$ is a natural axiom schema for the universe of sets. In particular it is a natural closure condition on $V$ and a natural generalization of $IFS(L).$ Here we shall prove the consistency of $ZFC\ +\ CIFS$ relative to the existence of a transitive model of $ZFC$ using the compactness theorem together with a class forcing.
math
1,865
Bounding and dominating number of families of functions on N
math.LO
We pursue the study of families of functions on the natural numbers, with emphasis here on the bounded families. The situation being more complicated than the unbounded case, we attack the problem by classifying the families according to their bounding and dominating numbers, the traditional scheme for gaps. Many open questions remain.
math
1,866
Sums of Darboux and continuous functions
math.LO
It is shown that that for every Darboux function $F$ there is a non-constant continuous function $f$ such that $F+f$ is still Darboux. It is shown to be consistent --- the model used is iterated Sacks forcing --- that for every Darboux function $F$ there is a nowhere constant continuous function $f$ such that $F+f$ is still Darboux. This answers questions raised by B.~Kirchiem and T.~Natkaniec who have shown that in various models of set theory there are universally bad Darboux functions, Darboux functions whose sum with any nowhere constant, continuous function fails to be Darboux.
math
1,867
Čech-Stone remainders of spaces that look like $[0,\infty)$
math.LO
We show that many spaces that look like the half~line~$\halfline=[0,\infty)$ have, under~$\CH$, a \v{C}ech-Stone-remainder that is homeomorphic to~$\Hstar$. We also show that $\CH$ is equivalent to the statement that all standard subcontinua of~$\Hstar$ are homeomorphic. The proofs use Model-theoretic tools like reduced products and elementary equivalence; rather than constructing homeomorphisms we show that the spaces in question have isomorphic bases for the closed sets.
math
1,868
The Ehrenfeucht-Fraisse-game of length omega_1
math.LO
Let (A) and (B) be two first order structures of the same vocabulary. We shall consider the Ehrenfeucht-Fra{i}sse-game of length omega_1 of A and B which we denote by G_{omega_1}(A,B). This game is like the ordinary Ehrenfeucht-Fraisse-game of L_{omega omega} except that there are omega_1 moves. It is clear that G_{omega_1}(A,B) is determined if A and B are of cardinality <= aleph_1. We prove the following results: Theorem A: If V=L, then there are models A and B of cardinality aleph_2 such that the game G_{omega_1}(A,B) is non-determined. Theorem B: If it is consistent that there is a measurable cardinal, then it is consistent that G_{omega_1}(A,B) is determined for all A and B of cardinality <= aleph_2. Theorem C: For any kappa >= aleph_3 there are A and B of cardinality kappa such that the game G_{omega_1}(A,B) is non-determined.
math
1,869
Strong measure zero sets without Cohen reals
math.LO
If ZFC is consistent, then each of the following are consistent with ZFC + 2^{{aleph_0}}= aleph_2 : 1.) X subseteq R is of strong measure zero iff |X| <= aleph_1 + there is a generalized Sierpinski set. 2.) The union of aleph_1 many strong measure zero sets is a strong measure zero set + there is a strong measure zero set of size aleph_2.
math
1,870
mu-complete Suslin trees on mu^+
math.LO
We prove that mu = mu^{< mu}, 2^mu = mu^+ and ``there is a non reflecting stationary subset of mu^+ composed of ordinals of cofinality < mu'' imply that there is a mu-complete Souslin tree on mu^+ .
math
1,871
An application of Shoenfield's absoluteness theorem to the theory of uniform distribution
math.LO
If (B_x: x in N) is a Borel family of sets, indexed by the Baire space N = omega^omega, all B_x have measure zero, and the family is increasing, then the union of all B_x also has measure zero. We give two proofs of this theorem: one in the language of set theory, using Shoenfield's theorem on Sigma-1-2 sets, the other in the language of probability theory, using von Neumann's selection theorem, and we apply the theorem to a question on completely uniformly distributed sequences.
math
1,872
Addendum to ``Maximal Chains in $\fomom$ and Ultrapowers of the Integers''
math.LO
Upon presenting the proof of Theorem 3.3 in "Maximal chains in $$ and ultrapowers of the integers" I discovered that it is not entirely correct and certainly some details should be added. I have therefore written an addendum to the paper and made it available by ftp. Unfortunately the published version will be somewhat wanting.
math
1,873
The structure of pleasant ideals
math.LO
Normal ideals on regular uncountable cardinals are familiar objects. We investigate ideals that are pleasant--while a normal ideal is closed under arbitrary diagonal unions, a pleasant ideal is closed only under diagonal unions indexed by sets that are elements of the ideal. We show any selective ideal extending the nonstationary ideal must be normal.
math
1,874
The canary tree
math.LO
A canary tree is a tree of cardinality the continuum which has no uncountable branch, but gains a branch whenever a stationary set is destroyed (without adding reals). Canary trees are important in infinitary model theory. The existence of a canary tree is independent of ZFC + GCH.
math
1,875
On CH + 2^{aleph_1}-> (alpha)^2_2 for alpha < omega_2
math.LO
We prove the consistency of ``CH + 2^{aleph_1} is arbitrarily large + 2^{aleph_1} not-> (omega_1 x omega)^2_2''. If fact, we can get 2^{aleph_1} not-> [omega_1 x omega]^2_{aleph_0}. In addition to this theorem, we give generalizations to other cardinals.
math
1,876
Dominating functions and graphs
math.LO
A graph is called dominating if its vertices can be labelled with integers in such a way that for every function f: omega-> omega the graph contains a ray whose sequence of labels eventually exceeds f. We obtain a characterization of these graphs by producing a small family of dominating graphs with the property that every dominating graph must contain some member of the family.
math
1,877
A saturated model of an unsuperstable theory of cardinality greater than its theory has the small index property
math.LO
A model M of cardinality lambda is said to have the small index property if for every G subseteq Aut(M) such that [Aut(M):G] <= lambda there is an A subseteq M with |A|< lambda such that Aut_A(M) subseteq G. We show that if M^* is a saturated model of an unsuperstable theory of cardinality > Th(M), then M^* has the small index property.
math
1,878
A model in which there are Jech-Kunen trees but there are no Kurepa trees
math.LO
By an omega_1 --tree we mean a tree of power omega_1 and height omega_1. We call an omega_1 --tree a Jech--Kunen tree if it has kappa --many branches for some kappa strictly between omega_1 and 2^{omega_1}. In this paper we construct the models of CH plus 2^{omega_1}> omega_2, in which there are Jech--Kunen trees and there are no Kurepa trees.
math
1,879
Peano Arithmetic may not be interpretable in the monadic theory of orders
math.LO
Gurevich and Shelah have shown that Peano Arithmetic cannot be interpreted in the monadic second-order theory of short chains (hence, in the monadic second-order theory of the real line). We show here that it is consistent that there is no interpretation even in the monadic second-order theory of all chains.
math
1,880
Consequences of arithmetic for set theory
math.LO
In this paper, we consider certain cardinals in ZF (set theory without AC, the Axiom of Choice). In ZFC (set theory with AC), given any cardinals C and D, either C <= D or D <= C. However, in ZF this is no longer so. For a given infinite set A consider Seq(A), the set of all sequences of A without repetition. We compare |Seq(A)|, the cardinality of this set, to |P(A)|, the cardinality of the power set of A. What is provable about these two cardinals in ZF? The main result of this paper is that ZF |- for all A: |Seq(A)| not= |P(A)| and we show that this is the best possible result. Furthermore, it is provable in ZF that if B is an infinite set, then |fin(B)|<|P(B)|, even though the existence for some infinite set B^* of a function f from fin(B^*) onto P(B^*) is consistent with ZF.
math
1,881
Universal graphs without large cliques
math.LO
We give some existence/nonexistence statements on universal graphs, which under GCH give a necessary and sufficient condition for the existence of a universal graph of size lambda with no K(kappa), namely, if either kappa is finite or cf(kappa)>cf(lambda). (Here K(kappa) denotes the complete graph on kappa vertices.) The special case when lambda^{< kappa}= lambda was first proved by F. Galvin. Next, we investigate the question that if there is no universal K(kappa)-free graph of size lambda then how many of these graphs embed all the other. It was known, that if lambda^{< lambda}= lambda (e.g., if lambda is regular and the GCH holds below lambda), and kappa = omega, then this number is lambda^+. We show that this holds for every kappa <= lambda of countable cofinality. On the other hand, even for kappa = omega_1, and any regular lambda >= omega_1 it is consistent that the GCH holds below lambda, 2^{lambda} is as large as we wish, and the above number is either lambda^+ or 2^{lambda}, so both extremes can actually occur.
math
1,882
On uniformly antisymmetric functions
math.LO
We show that there is always a uniformly antisymmetric f:A-> {0,1} if A subset R is countable. We prove that the continuum hypothesis is equivalent to the statement that there is an f:R-> omega with |S_x| <= 1 for every x in R. If the continuum is at least aleph_n then there exists a point x such that S_x has at least 2^n-1 elements. We also show that there is a function f:Q-> {0,1,2,3} such that S_x is always finite, but no such function with finite range on R exists
math
1,883
Ultrafilters: Where topological dynamics = algebra = combinatorics
math.LO
We survey some connections between topological dynamics, semigroups of ultrafilters, and combinatorics. As an application, we give a proof, based on ideas of Bergelson and Hindman, of the Hales-Jewett partition theorem.
math
1,884
Evasion and prediction --- the Specker phenomenon and Gross spaces
math.LO
We study the set--theoretic combinatorics underlying the following two algebraic phenomena. (1) A subgroup G leq Z^omega exhibits the Specker phenomenon iff every homomorphism G to Z maps almost all unit vectors to 0. Let se be the size of the smallest G leq Z^omega exhibiting the Specker phenomenon. (2) Given an uncountably dimensional vector space E equipped with a symmetric bilinear form Phi over an at most countable field KK, (E,Phi) is strongly Gross iff for all countably dimensional U leq E, we have dim(U^perp) leq omega. Blass showed that the Specker phenomenon is closely related to a combinatorial phenomenon he called evading and predicting. We prove several additional results (both theorems of ZFC and independence proofs) about evading and predicting as well as se, and relate a Luzin--style property associated with evading to the existence of strong Gross spaces.
math
1,885
Combinatorial properties of classical forcing notions
math.LO
We discuss the effect of adding a single real (for various forcing notions adding reals) on cardinal invariants associated with the continuum (like the unbounding or the dominating number or the cardinals related to measure and category on the real line). For random and Cohen forcing, this question was investigated by Cicho'n and Pawlikowski; for Hechler forcing, by Judah, Shelah and myself. We show here: (1) adding an eventually different or a localization real adjoins a Luzin set of size continuum and a mad family of size omega_1; (2) Laver and Mathias forcing collapse the dominating number to omega_1 --- consequences: (A) CON(d=omega_1 + unif(L) = unif (M) = kappa = 2^omega) for any regular uncountable kappa; (B) Two Laver or Mathias reals added iteratively always force CH (even diamond); (C) Sigma^1_4-Mathias-absoluteness implies the Sigma^1_3- Ramsey property; (3) Miller's rational perfect set forcing preserves the axiom MA(sigma-centered).
math
1,886
The additivity of porosity ideals
math.LO
We show that several sigma-ideals related to porous sets have additivity omega_1 and cofinality 2^omega. This answers a question addressed by Miroslav Repick'y.
math
1,887
A New Proof of Kunen's Inconsistency
math.LO
Using elementary pcf, we show that there is no $j:V\to M,$ $M$ transitive, $j\lambda =\lambda >crit(j),$ $j^{\prime \prime}\lambda \in M.$
math
1,888
Questions and answers -- a category arising in linear logic, complexity theory, and set theory
math.LO
A category used by de Paiva to model linear logic also occurs in Vojtas's analysis of cardinal characteristics of the continuum. Its morphisms have been used in describing reductions between search problems in complexity theory. We describe this category and how it arises in these various contexts. We also show how these contexts suggest certain new multiplicative connectives for linear logic. Perhaps the most interesting of these is a sequential composition suggested by the set-theoretic application.
math
1,889
Possible Behaviours of the Reflection Ordering of Stationary Sets
math.LO
If $S,T$ are stationary subsets of a regular uncountable cardinal $\kappa$, we say that $S$ reflects fully in $T$, $S<T$, if for almost all $\alpha \in T$ (except a nonstationary set) $S \cap \alpha$ is stationary in $\alpha .$ This relation is known to be a well founded partial ordering. We say that a given poset $P$ is realized by the reflection ordering if there is a maximal antichain $\langle X_p ; p \in P \rangle$ of stationary subsets of $Reg(\kappa)$ so that $$\forall p,q \in P \; \forall S\subseteq X_p, T\subseteq X_q \text{ stationary}:(S<T \leftrightarrow p<_P q ) .$$ We prove that if $\kappa$ is $\Cal P _2 \kappa -$strong and $P$ an arbitrary well founded poset of cardinality $\leq \k^+$ then there is a generic extension where P is realized by the reflection ordering on $\kappa .$
math
1,890
On the divisible parts of quotient groups
math.LO
Techniques of combinatorial set theory are applied to the following algebraic problem. Suppose G is an abelian group such that, for all countable subgroups C, the divisible part of the quotient G/C is countable. What can one conclude about the size of the divisible part of G/K when the cardinality of the subgroup K is a given uncountable cardinal?
math
1,891
Is game semantics necessary?
math.LO
We discuss the extent to which game semantics is implicit in the formalism of linear logic and in the intuitions underlying linear logic.
math
1,892
How to win some simple iteration games
math.LO
We introduce two new iteration games: the game G, which is a strengthening of the weak iteration game, and the game G+, which is somewhat stronger than G but weaker than the full iteration game of length omega_1. For a countable M elementarily embeddable in some V_{eta}, we can show that II wins G(M,omega_1) and that I does not win the G+(M).
math
1,893
IST is more than an algorithm to prove ZFC theorems
math.LO
There is a sentence in the language of IST, Nelson's internal set theory, which is not equivalent in IST to a sentence in the ZFC language. Thus the Reduction algorithm of Nelson, that converts bounded IST formulas with standard parameters to provably (in IST) equivalent formulas in the ZFC language, cannot be extended to all formulas of the IST language. Therefore, certain IST sentences are "meaningless" from the point of view of the standard universe.
math
1,894
Examples for Souslin forcing
math.LO
We give a model where there is a ccc Souslin forcing which does not satisfy the Knaster condition. Next, we present a model where there is a sigma-linked not sigma-centered Souslin forcing such that all its small subsets are sigma-centered but Martin Axiom fails for this order. Furthermore, we construct a totally nonhomogeneous Souslin forcing and we build a Souslin forcing which is proper but not ccc that does not contain a perfect set of mutually incompatible conditions. Finally we show that ccc Sigma^1_2-notions of forcing may not be indestructible ccc.
math
1,895
On hidden extenders
math.LO
A model with a sequence of indiscernibles depending on a particular precovering set is constructed.The initial assumption is as follows: for every n<omega the set {alpha | o(alpha)=alpha^+n } is unbounded in kappa.
math
1,896
Iterated Class Forcing
math.LO
In this paper we isolate the notion of Stratified class forcing and show that Stratification implies cofinality-preservation and is preserved by iterations with the appropriate support. Many familiar class forcings are stratified and therefore can be simultaneously iterated without changing cofinalities, provided the proper support is used. Easton forcing, Backward Easton forcings and some modifications of Jensen coding are stratified. Jensen coding is not stratified but instead obeys a related property, Delta-Stratification, which is also preservedby iteration with an appropriate larger support.
math
1,897
A combinatorial forcing for coding the universe by a real when there are no sharps
math.LO
Assuming 0# does not exist, we present a combinatorial approach to Jensen's method of coding by a real. The forcing uses combinatorial consequences of fine structure (including the Covering Lemma, in various guises), but makes no direct appeal to fine structure itself.
math
1,898
Applications of cohomology to questions in set theory i: hausdorff gaps
math.LO
We explore an application of homological algebra to set theoretic objects by developing a cohomology theory for Hausdorff gaps. The cohomology theory is introduced with enough generality to be applicable to other questions in set theory. For gaps, this leads to a natural equivalence notion about which we answer questions by constructing many simultaneous gaps. The first result is proved by constructing countably many gaps such that the union of any combination corresponding to a subset of $\omega$ is again a gap. This is done in ZFC. New combinatorial hypotheses related to club ($\clubsuit$) are introduced to prove the second result which increases the number of gaps to $\aleph_1$. The presentation of these results does not depend on the development of the cohomology theory. Additionally, the notion of an incollapsible gap is introduced and the existence of such a gap is shown to be independent of ZFC.
math
1,899
Ultrafilters on omega
math.LO
A variety of classes of naturally arising ultrafilters on omega is discussed, and the question is raised whether it is consistent that the classes are empty. Since all the classes contain the P-point ultrafilters, a negative answer would greatly extend the famous theorem of Shelah.
math